Under
capitalism, each individual capital shares in the total surplus value
produced, not on the basis of the surplus value it produces itself,
but on a proportionate basis to its share of the total social
capital. This is the consequence of market prices being based not upon
exchange values, as in pre-capitalist commodity production and
exchange, but on the basis of prices of production. As a result, a
merchant capitalist does not produce any surplus value, but they
obtain a share of the total surplus value produced in society,
because this capital, like every other capital, obtains the average
rate of profit. The same is true of money-dealing capital, which is
only a form of merchant capital. Money dealing capital, as Marx sets out only performs the same functions as do the commercial workers employed by productive-capital. They carry out the function of keeping accounts of transactions, they make payments and take in receipts. The specialist firms that become established to carry out these functions, obtain profits in the same way as any other merchant capital, i.e. because they are capital, they charge a price for carrying out this function, which is paid by the productive-capitalist, because the specialist firm performs this function at lower cost.
But, this is
quite different when it comes to money-lending capital,
interest-bearing capital, as opposed to money-dealing capital. The
difference is often overlooked, because it becomes natural for the
money-dealing capitalists to also become money-lending capitalists, and also because money-lending capitalists can only lend money via the medium of the money-dealing capitalist. Banks for example, act as money-dealing capitalists by processing payments through the clearing of cheques. They make profits on this activity as merchant capital, by charging for carrying out the function, but they also take in deposits from lenders, and make loans to borrowers. In this latter function, they become a centralised representative of interest-bearing capital. Productive-capital, commodity-capital, and money-capital are all
forms of capital-value within the context of the circuit of
industrial capital, and each obtains the average profit on that
basis. Interest-bearing capital, exists outside that circuit. It
does not, therefore, obtain the average profit. It is not in reality
capital, but only fictitious capital. What it obtains is not a
profit, but only a price for the commodity it sells, and that
commodity is capital itself, or more precisely the use value of
capital, the ability to self-expand.
In this
respect, interest-bearing capital, capital as a commodity, is like
labour-power. Both are commodities that are sold in the market, and
whose price is a price based upon the use value they provide, the use-value of self-expanding value. It is based on that use value, in the sense that nothing can be a commodity and have a price unless it provides some form of use value. Labour-power
provides this use value, because it creates new value that is greater
than the value of the labour-power itself. But, because all capital
obtains a share in the total surplus value, all capital possesses the
use value of being able to self-expand in value. A capitalist who
owns a machine, and uses it to process material, to make commodities,
even if they employ no labour-power whatsoever, and so produces no
surplus value, will still see the value of their capital self-expand,
i.e. they will make profits, solely because, as capital, it shares in
the total surplus value produced, and they will obtain this share as
profits, because of the price of production of the commodities they
sell.
Anyone who
possesses capital, therefore, possesses the ability to participate in
the sharing out of the total surplus value of the society. And, for
anyone who does not possess capital, but who seeks it, in order to
obtain this use value, of being self-expanding value, there is a
price to pay. Suppose, I am an engineer, but I do not own a lathe.
I cannot then undertake production so as to be able to produce a
commodity to sell, and thereby share in the total surplus value.
However, if A owns a lathe, they may be prepared to loan this machine
to me. I can then use it to process materials, produce commodities,
and thereby make profits. What I pay for, in interest, is not a
price for use of the machine as a machine, but a price for use of the
machine as capital.
If the value
of the machine is £10,000, and the average rate of profit is 10%,
then, assuming I sell my output at its price of production, this
£10,000 of capital, represented by the machine, will bring me £1,000
of profit. That is its use value, as capital. But, A, will not sell
this use value to me for nothing. They will seek to obtain a price
for this use value. Clearly, that price cannot be equal to the value
of the machine itself, of £10,000, because, if I had £10,000 of
money-capital, I would have simply bought the machine, rather than
needing to loan it. Moreover, if A had paid £10,000 for the
machine, they would make nothing from loaning it to me, for a total
payment of £10,000, over its lifetime. By loaning it to me, they are
standing out of being able to use it as capital, and make 10% profit
themselves.
The use
value of the lathe, as a machine, is a function of its ability to
process metal. But, the use value of the lathe as capital, is its
ability to self-expand in value. The value of the machine is
determined by the labour-time required for its production. But, the
machine, as capital, as an ability to self-expand value, has no
value, because it is not the product of labour. Like land, which
also has no value, because it is not the product of labour, however,
it is a use value, a commodity, which is bought and sold, and which,
therefore, has a market price.
I am not
buying the use value of the machine, which is represented by its
value of £10,000, I am only buying the use value of the machine as
capital, as something which has the ability to expand value, by
obtaining a proportionate share of total social surplus value. Where
the price of every other commodity revolves around its exchange
value, and under capitalism its price of production, therefore,
determined ultimately by its value, the price of capital, like the
price of land can have no such locus, because it has no such value.
The market price of capital as a commodity, like the price of land,
is determined solely by the interaction of supply and demand, but is
then regulated by an upper and lower limit. That market price for the use value of land is rent, and for capital is the rate rate of interest.
As Marx
makes clear, therefore, in describing the rate of interest, as the
price of loanable capital, this loanable capital is defined in money
terms, because, in order to make rational calculations, all capital
value must be expressed in money, as unit of account, but it can
relate just as easily to capital loaned in the form of machines,
material and so on. The lower limit for the price of capital is
zero, because no one will make available the use value of capital
without demanding a price for it. The upper limit is determined, by
the rate of profit, because no one will borrow capital if the price
for doing so is greater than the return on that capital.
2 comments:
Natural resources like the use value of land are never real commodities, as they are not the result of the expenditure of labor power under capitalist conditions. Their "commodity representation" under capitalism makes these what I call "pseudo-commodities", accomplished necessarily by means of the credit system, hence the apparent homology with constant capital advanced for production. However the real value basis for this representation is *rent*, capitalized at the mortgage rate of interest so as to represent land "price", "prima facie irrational" as Marx correctly stated. Rent is not an exchange relation. Rent is a *tributary* social relation of production, like taxes. The regulation of the magnitude of rent by the law of value in capitalist production does not negate this fundamental fact of rent as social relation. And this means of course that land as use value is transformed into landed property not via commodity production, but by so-called "extra-economic" means, i.e. by the armed force of the state, you know, the force that rounded up the indigenous peoples of North America and marched them into open-air concentration camps labeled "reservations". Hence also the element of so-called primitive accumulation involved in the subsumption of rent to capital. The main feudal relation of production becomes a most powerful lever for this "primitive" accumulation under capitalism, on an ongoing basis.
That differs from means of production produced as commodities. They have (exchange) value and can autonomously circulate as commodities or commodity-capital independently (theoretically here) of the credit system. Landed property under capitalism *cannot* even theoretically circulate without the credit system. Constant fixed capital advanced for means of production that are placed into production have no exchange value while in production, true, but can have value outside of production *in some rational proportion* to their original production price. This is never the case with land, whose real value is ex post facto mediated by use (rent), and its "price" mediated by the credit system on this real basis.
Use of labor power -> commodity exchange
Use of land -> rent tribute
That's why I prefer the term "fictitious capital" to describe credit advanced for the formation of land "price" at interest. I would also include state treasuries, as they share the same fundamental tributary basis in taxes.
That is also why I prefer the term used by finance itself - derivative capital - for stocks, corporate bonds and other such securities. Not in the narrow technical sense, but literally in that these are (securitized) money capitals, capital in commodity form, circulating as such because they can make a claim on the total surplus value by virtue of the use value of money.
Matthew,
Thanks for your comments. It would take too long to reply to everything you say here, and I will be dealing with all these points in various places later. However, although I think there are problems with Marx's theory of rent, I prefer his definitions of fictitious capital, and his analysis of capitalist rent, which I have outlined, to those you propose here.
Marx uses the term "commodity" to describe loanable money-capital, i.e. fictitious capital, just as he describes the way land becomes a commodity, because although they have no value, they are not products, because they have not been produced by labour, they are bought and sold in the market like any other commodity, and as a consequence, they have a market price - interest and rent.
Your analysis of rent is wrong for the reasons Marx sets out against the bourgeois economists who use the same kind of ahistorical formulation you use here. The difference between feudal rent, and capitalist rent, as Marx sets out in the chapter describing pre-capitalist forms of rent, and as he sets out in the final chapters of Volume III, describing production and distribution relations, is precisely that capitalist rent is NOT a form of tribute, like taxes, but arises directly from capitalist productive relations, on the basis of the existence of surplus profits.
Moreover, as Marx sets out the value of land is not based upon the "mortgage rate of interest" but on the average rate of interest. That is so, precisely because, as marx sets out, under capitalism, loanable money-capital is able to move to wherever it can obtain the highest rate of interest. If yields on bonds are higher than rental yields, capital will sell land and buy bonds, and so on.
Moreover, as Marx describes, this transformation of land into a commodity precedes the use of credit on a large scale. The old feudal land ownership broke down, precisely because the development of capitalist farmers, through the process of differentiation of the peasantry, as well as the capitalistic purchase of land, by capitalists who had made their fortunes in the towns, turned this land not into something that was passed down through families, but something which was simply bought and sold dependent upon the current yield it would return on the investment of the capital.
I don't know why you say fixed capital has no exchange value whilst in production, and the idea that this value outside of production is related to its original production price is simply wrong. As Marx sets out, its precisely because fixed capital DOES continue to have an exchange value "fixed" within it at the end of its function in each production process that gives it its nature as fixed rather than circulating capital.
Moreover, as Marx repeatedly states, and as he sets out as being totally required for his theory of social reproduction to work, the value of the commodities that comprise the capital used in current production is defined by its current reproduction cost, not its original production cost, or historic price. If that is not the case, his requirement stated in the schemas of reproduction in Volume II, and in his analysis at the end of Volume III cannot work, because the commodities that comprise the constant and variable-capital (means of production and consumption) must be physically reproduced for social reproduction to occur, and that can only occur, if they are physically allocated out of the current production, which means at their current production costs, determined by current levels of productivity, which requires them to be valued at current not historic prices.
Post a Comment