In memory of the late, great Fontella Bass who died the other day.
Saturday, 29 December 2012
Friday, 28 December 2012
The Value Form
The Value Form is the way in which the Value of a Use Value is expressed in terms of a quantity of some other Use Value. The Value Form comprises two parts of an equation. The first part is the Use Value, whose Value is being expressed. This is the Relative Form Of Value. The quantity of the other Use Value against, which it is being equated i.e. used to measure it, is the Equivalent Form Of Value.
As a comparison we might say, a Field is 100 metres long. But, a table is 2 metres long. Using, metre as the measure of length, both the field and the table have a length in metres that is unaffected by any other relation. Whatever happens to the table has no consequence for the length of the field and vice versa. But, once we establish a relation between these two things, then changes in the length of one do have a consequence for this relation.
So, we can say that:
1 Field = 50 tables i.e. both these two things have the same length of 100 metres.
Here,
1 Field is the "Relative Form of Length", whereas 50 tables is the "Equivalent Form of Length".
But, if a change in either or both of these two occurs, it clearly disturbs this relation. If tables are reduced in size to 1 metre, then the equation will be,
1 Field = 100 tables.
In other words, length measured by a constant metric (metres) is only affected by changes to the thing being measured. However, length when measured against some other standard is affected both by changes to itself, and changes to the thing against which it is being compared.
The same is true in relation to the Value Form. Value is measured in terms of Abstract Labour-time. The Value of something can only change if the labour-time required for its production changes. But, its Value relative to something else changes not only with changes to its own Value, but also changes in the Value of the thing against which it is being compared.
This Value Form analysis, Marx uses to demonstrate the way commodities develop as Use Values produced for the purpose of Exchange. Their Value, then takes the form of Exchange Value, which is represented in this Value Form. Marx demonstrates how logically and historically this Value Form evolves, so that ultimately a single commodity arises as a Universal Equivalent Form of Value, and this commodity is then transformed into Money. The historical and logical development is:
For further discussion on this see: Capital I, Chapter 3
As a comparison we might say, a Field is 100 metres long. But, a table is 2 metres long. Using, metre as the measure of length, both the field and the table have a length in metres that is unaffected by any other relation. Whatever happens to the table has no consequence for the length of the field and vice versa. But, once we establish a relation between these two things, then changes in the length of one do have a consequence for this relation.
So, we can say that:
1 Field = 50 tables i.e. both these two things have the same length of 100 metres.
Here,
1 Field is the "Relative Form of Length", whereas 50 tables is the "Equivalent Form of Length".
But, if a change in either or both of these two occurs, it clearly disturbs this relation. If tables are reduced in size to 1 metre, then the equation will be,
1 Field = 100 tables.
In other words, length measured by a constant metric (metres) is only affected by changes to the thing being measured. However, length when measured against some other standard is affected both by changes to itself, and changes to the thing against which it is being compared.
The same is true in relation to the Value Form. Value is measured in terms of Abstract Labour-time. The Value of something can only change if the labour-time required for its production changes. But, its Value relative to something else changes not only with changes to its own Value, but also changes in the Value of the thing against which it is being compared.
This Value Form analysis, Marx uses to demonstrate the way commodities develop as Use Values produced for the purpose of Exchange. Their Value, then takes the form of Exchange Value, which is represented in this Value Form. Marx demonstrates how logically and historically this Value Form evolves, so that ultimately a single commodity arises as a Universal Equivalent Form of Value, and this commodity is then transformed into Money. The historical and logical development is:
- Use Values are sporadically brought into relation one with another, as primitive tribal communities come into contact e.g. in wedding ceremonies. So the Value Form is like that above:
1 ox = 3 goats
1 camel = 5 sheep
and so on. - The more these communities develop and come into more regular contact so that trade begins, the more each group has some item it regularly trades. At this stage, trade is still done by the community, rather than by individual traders. The Value Form here represents this transition, so the thing regularly traded assumes the role of Relative Form of Value.
1 ox = 3 goats
1 ox = 7 sheep
1 ox = 2 camels
and so on. - As trade develops further so that a wider range of Use Values are frequently traded, its necessary to be able to compare the Values of each of these regularly traded goods easily against some standard. Consequently, one commodity, frequently the one that was most traded like cattle, or salt, is singled out so that it can act as the measure of all these other goods. So,
3 goats = 1 ox
7 sheep = 1 ox
2 camels = 1 ox.
So now, the thing most frequently traded assumes the position of Equivalent Form of Value. Its limitation in its present state can be seen from the above. If I want to know the (Exchange) Value of 1 goat, it is equivalent to 1/3 ox!
For further discussion on this see: Capital I, Chapter 3
Labels:
Marxist Economic Theory
The Relative Form of Value
Value is measured in labour-time, but Exchange Value is the relation of the Value of one Use Value compared to a quantity of some other. This relation is expressed in the Value Form. The Value form comprises two parts. The first part is the Relative Form of Value, the second is the Equivalent Form of Value.
So, for example 1 metre of Linen = 10 kilos of Sugar.
Here, 1 metre of Linen is the Relative Form of Value. Its value is being expressed relative to a quantity of some other use value - here 10 kilos of Sugar, which is its equivalent.
This relation can only exist because both contain value. Linen and sugar are clearly two different things, which cannot be compared. However, the fact that both contain value, means that this common thing value can be compared. Because both linen and sugar contain different amounts of value, i.e. both require different amounts of labour-time to produce, the only way in which an equal amount of value can appear on both sides of the equation is if the value of the 1 metre of linen, is equated with the quantity of sugar that contains this same amount of value.
The Relative Form of Value can remain constant, whilst its Equivalent Form changes. For example,
1 metre of linen = 100 kilos of feathers.
Even the Equivalent Form measured in the same use value can change. For example,
1 metre of linen = 12 kilos of sugar.
That can be for several reasons.
- The value of linen could rise, because more labour-time is now required for its production.
- The value of sugar could fall, because less labour-time is now required for its production.
- The value of linen could rise, and the value of sugar fall.
- The value of both linen and sugar might rise, but the value of linen rise by more than that of sugar.
- The value of both linen and sugar might fall, but the value of linen fall by less than that of sugar.
By the same token, the value of both linen and sugar might rise or fall, and yet the Equivalent Form remain constant, because both have moved in the same proportion.
For example, suppose the value of 1 metre of linen = 10 hours labour-time.
The value of 100 kilos of sugar is also = 10 hours of labour-time. So,
1 metre linen = 100 kilos sugar. But, suppose a rise in productivity means both linen and sugar can be produced in half the previous time. Now, the value of 1 metre of linen = 5 hours labour-time, and the value of 100 kilos of sugar also = 5 hours labour-time. The value of both linen and sugar has been halved. But, we still have:
1 metre linen = 100 kilos sugar.
The value has been halved, but the exchange value of linen remains constant measured in its Equivalent Form, sugar.
For a fuller discussion see.
Labels:
Marxist Economic Theory
Dialectics
Dialectics is a system of
logic based on the idea that reality involves continuous change. All
continuous change i.e. movement is fundamentally contradictory. If
we take any body in motion, for example a falling ball, it is
impossible to define its position exactly, because any such attempt
involves trying to identify its position at a point in time.
However, because time is continuous, there can be no such thing as a
point in time, because however small we attempt to make this point,
it will always have some duration – a beginning and end.
Consequently, it will always be true that the ball will be at one
position at the beginning of this time period, and somewhere else at
the end.
The only point in time where
this would not be the case would be one that had no duration, no
dimension, a zero in time. But, in the real world there is no such
thing as a zero of time. Time by its essence is continuous.
Consequently, when we reduce reality down to these quantum levels we
find that it is contradictory. We find that for any period or point
of time, the ball is at two different positions.
This is at odds with
Aristotelian Logic based on the syllogism, which insists that no such
contradiction can exist. It is based on the fundamental proposition
A = A, and consequently A does not = not A (-A). Trotsky in
A Petit-Bourgeois Opposition In The Socialist Workers Party
sets out what is wrong with this when he challenged the adoption of
syllogistic logic by Burnham and Shachtman.
“I will here attempt to
sketch the substance of the problem in a very concise form. The
Aristotelian logic of the simple syllogism starts from the
proposition that “A” is equal to “A.” This postulate is
accepted as an axiom for a multitude of practical human actions and
elementary generalizations. But in reality “A” is not equal to
“A.” This is easy to prove if we observe these two letters under
a lens – they are quite different from each other. But, one can
object, the question is not of the size or the form of the letters,
since they are only symbols for equal quantities, for instance, a
pound of sugar. The objection is beside the point; in reality a pound
of sugar is never equal to a pound of sugar – a more delicate scale
always discloses a difference. Again one can object: but a pound of
sugar is equal to itself. Neither is this true – all bodies change
uninterruptedly in size, weight, color, etc. They are never equal to
themselves. A sophist will respond that a pound of sugar is equal to
itself “at any given moment.” Aside from the extremely dubious
practical value of this “axiom,” it does not withstand
theoretical criticism either. How should we really conceive the word
“moment”? If it is an infinitesimal interval of time, then a
pound of sugar is subjected during the course of that “moment” to
inevitable changes. Or is the “moment” a purely mathematical
abstraction, that is, a zero of time? But everything exists in time;
and existence itself is an uninterrupted process of transformation;
time is consequently a fundamental element of existence. Thus the
axiom “A” is equal to “A” signifies that a thing is equal to
itself if it does not change, that is, if it does not exist...
Dialectical thinking is
related to vulgar thinking in the same way that a motion picture is
related to a still photograph. The motion picture does not outlaw the
still photograph but combines a series of them according to the laws
of motion...
We call our dialectic, materialist, since its roots
are neither in heaven nor in the depths of our “free will,” but
in objective reality, in nature.”
This contradiction can be
seen in many different spheres. For example, a central postulate of
geometry is based upon the tangent. A tangent touches the
circumference of a circle at a point. At this point, therefore, the
angle of the circle is equal to the angle of the tangent. But, the
tangent is a straight line. Its angle is 180 degrees. So, how can the
circle be equal to a straight line? Geometry avoids this
contradiction, by theorising a point as a zero point, but a zero
point in space is in reality as meaningless as a zero point in time.
It can only exist in the world of ideas, as an abstraction, not in
the real material world. Everything materially existing in space has
dimension, just as much as everything existing in time. Indeed,
thanks to Einstein we know that space and time are interchangeable as
part of the space-time continuum.
The same contradiction can
be seen in the fact that light can be both a wave and a particle.
Quantum mechanics has demonstrated that at a quantum level the
certainty required by syllogistic logic does not exist, and instead
we have the
Uncertainty Principle.
This may be true for time at
a quantum level too. For example, we accept that the
Arrow Of Time
points only in one direction. However, it is possible that reduced
to a quantum level, time's arrow too may be uncertain. It could move
forward or backward with varying probabilities. Consequently, any
concept of a point in time at this level would incorporate in itself,
the basic idea of the dialectic that the present is itself a
contradictory unity of the past and future, in the process of
resolution of this contradiction, the resultant being forward motion.
Hegel
based his dialectic on his Idealist
philosophy. That is that the material world is merely a reflection
of the world of ideas. The logical conclusion of Idealism is in fact
Solipsism.
If there is no such thing as the material world outside what the
human mind creates, then that applies equally to every material thing
including other human beings. Indeed that would extend to our own
physical bodies. So we are left with a reality in which all that
exists is our own mind!
Hegel believed that the
Dialectic was the unfolding of The Idea, and its manifestation in the
material world. The Idea (or God) established the rules, which could
be uncovered. Philosopher Kings uncovered these rules, and in doing
so the Idea was revealed. The Philosopher Kings (The Prussian State
for Hegel) then applied these rules in the material world, so that
the material world itself mirrored the unfolding of the idea. The
unfolding of The Idea was itself a process of movement, and,
therefore governed by the Dialectic.
Marx as a Materialist
rejected this mysticism. He and Engels both recognised independently
that the material world existed whether or not the human mind
existed. Indeed, the human mind was a physical element, a material
thing itself. But, both also recognised that it was the nature of
this material reality that was itself contradictory, precisely
because the nature of matter is that it exists in time, and is
continuously, therefore, changing. Rather than it being The Idea,
which is unfolding, and then being reflected in the material world,
it is the other way around. Material reality is constantly changing,
and this causes Men's Minds to change, their perception of that
reality to change, and consequently their ideas to change.
Labels:
Marxism,
Philosophy
Thursday, 27 December 2012
Capital I, Chapter 17 - Part 2
LENGTH OF THE WORKING-DAY AND INTENSITY OF LABOUR CONSTANT. PRODUCTIVENESS OF LABOUR VARIABLE.
-
Marx
identifies three laws.
- A working day, of a given length, always produces the same amount of new value. (NB. As with the statements above, this assumes, of course, that the labour-time expended was socially necessary. Labour-time expended on production that is not demanded, which is faulty such as a failed crop, for example, does not create new value, or creates new value only of a diminished amount.)
Value is a measure of socially necessary labour-time. If a greater quantity of items are produce during this period, because the labour has become more productive, this does not change the amount of value produced in this time, it only means that value is spread across a larger number of items so that the value of each is reduced.
- “Surplus value and the value of labour-power vary in opposite directions. A variation in the productiveness of labour, its increase or diminution, causes a variation in the opposite direction in the value of labour-power, and in the same direction in surplus value.” (p 487)A working day of say 10 hours produces a constant amount of new value = 10 hours, assuming we are talking about average labour. If £1 = 1 hour, this equals £10. This time, and this new value is divided into necessary and surplus labour-time, the value of labour-power (wages) and surplus value. Consequently, if one of the components of this constant quantity rises, the other must fall. If initially, they are equal, £5 wages, and £5 surplus value, then if wages rise to £6 (because the cost of food, clothing, shelter etc. rises) then surplus value must fall to £4. Similarly, surplus value cannot rise from £5 to £6, without wages falling to £4.
But, wages are fixed by the costs of reproducing the labour power. Marx assumes here that they cannot fall below the value of labour power. In other words, we have two constant magnitudes – the total value of the 10 hours = £10, and the value of the labour power. Everything else remaining the same, only the surplus value is a variable quantity.
However, as was demonstrated previously, the value of labour-power can fall if the value of necessaries fall, or if the productivity of labour rises, reducing the portion of the working day required to reproduce it. If the productivity of labour rises by 40%, then what previously took five hours to produce, can now be produced in three. So, the workers necessaries can now be produced in three hours = £3. That means that surplus labour-time can rise from five hours to 7 hours, surplus value rises from £5 to £7, but the workers real wages remain constant.
“It follows from this, that an increase in the productiveness of labour causes a fall in the value of labour-power and a consequent rise in surplus value, while, on the other hand, a decrease in such productiveness causes a rise in the value of labour-power, and a fall in surplus value.” (p 488)
This law
was first developed by Ricardo, but Marx correctly points out that he
failed to note that although the two components move in opposite
directions by the same amount, they do not move in the same
proportion. That depends on the original amounts. For example, if
originally wages were £4 and surplus value £6, a 50% rise in
productivity would reduce wages to £2, and increase surplus value to
£8. However, this a 2/4 = 50% reduction in wages, but only a 2/6 =
33.3% rise in surplus value. The opposite is the case had the
original figures been reversed.
3)“Increase
or diminution in surplus value is always consequent on, and never the
cause of, the corresponding diminution or increase in the value of
labour-power.” (p 488)
Marx also
notes here,
John Ramsay McCulloch |
This
presages Marx’s analysis of “Capital in General” in Volume III,
where Marx examines the division of surplus value between different
sections of the exploiting classes – Interest to Money Capital,
Profit to Productive and Commercial Capital, Rent to Landed Property,
and Taxes to the Capitalist State.
“If,
then, as we have already seen, there can be no change of absolute
magnitude in the value of labour-power, and in surplus value,
unaccompanied by a change in their relative magnitudes, so now it
follows that no change in their relative magnitudes is possible,
without a previous change in the absolute magnitude of the value of
labour-power.” (p 489)
Fordism worked by reducing the value of labour power via continual increases in productivity, whilst ensuring an annual increase in real wages. |
“The
amount of this fall, the lowest limit of which is 3 shillings (the
new value of labour-power), depends on the relative weight, which the
pressure of capital on the one side, and the resistance of the
labourer on the other, throws into the scale.” (p 489)
It is here
that the organisation of the workers, into Trades Unions, was able to
play a role, at the margin, in the determination of wages in the
short term. But, it is only marginal and only short term, for the
reasons Marx and Engels set out.
Engels
wrote,
“The
history of these Unions is a long series of defeats of the
working-men, interrupted by a few isolated victories. All these
efforts naturally cannot alter the economic law according to which
wages are determined by the relation between supply and demand in the
labour market. Hence the Unions remain powerless against all great
forces which influence this relation. In a commercial crisis the
Union itself must reduce wages or dissolve wholly; and in a time of
considerable increase in the demand for labour, it cannot fix the
rate of wages higher than would be reached spontaneously by the
competition of the capitalists among themselves.”
Whilst
Marx wrote,
“I
think I have shown that their struggles for the standard of wages are
incidents inseparable from the whole wages system, that in 99 cases
out of 100 their efforts at raising wages are only efforts at
maintaining the given value of labour, and that the necessity of
debating their price with the capitalist is inherent to their
condition of having to sell themselves as commodities. By cowardly
giving way in their everyday conflict with capital, they would
certainly disqualify themselves for the initiating of any larger
movement.
At the same time, and quite apart from the
general servitude involved in the wages system, the working class
ought not to exaggerate to themselves the ultimate working of these
everyday struggles. They ought not to forget that they are fighting
with effects, but not with the causes of those effects; that they are
retarding the downward movement, but not changing its direction; that
they are applying palliatives, not curing the malady. They ought,
therefore, not to be exclusively absorbed in these unavoidable
guerilla fights incessantly springing up from the never ceasing
encroachments of capital or changes of the market. They ought to
understand that, with all the miseries it imposes upon them, the
present system simultaneously engenders the material
conditions and the social forms
necessary for an economical reconstruction of society. Instead of the
conservative motto: “A
fair day's wage for a fair day's work!”
they ought to inscribe on their banner the revolutionary
watchword: “Abolition of the wages
system!"
In the end, as Marx and Engels set out, it is the demand for and
supply of labour power which determines, and that is a consequence of
the rate of accumulation of capital, which in turn depends on the
rate of profit, and the opportunity for investing new capital in
profitable ventures.
Marx also gives a variation of the situation described previously,
where a rise in productivity allows real wages to remain constant,
while nominal wages fall and surplus value rises. If productivity
doubles, but nominal wages remain constant, then the working day
remains 5 hours for wages, and 5 hours for surplus value. But now,
twice as many Use Values can be bought with these £5's. The
workers' real wage has doubled, and the capitalist can buy twice as
many luxuries, or twice as much constant capital, to expand
production.
In the post war boom, Fordism meant workers real wages rose sharply, and they acquired many more Use Values, but rises in productivity meant, profits rose even more. |
As stated
previously, this was precisely the basis upon which Fordism operated
in the 20th Century, particularly after WWII. These three
laws, set out by Marx, were originally developed by Ricardo, but Marx
sets out the limitations of Ricardo's understanding of them.
Ricardo does
not take account of changes in the length of the working day, or its
intensity, so only the productivity of labour acts as a variable
factor. Ricardo does not analyse the source or nature of surplus
value, separate from his analysis of Interest, Rent and Profit.
Instead he simply takes its existence for granted. It also leads him
to confuse the rate of profit with the rate of surplus value. The
latter is surplus value expressed as a proportion of wages, whilst
the former is surplus value expressed as a proportion of total
capital advanced.
“I
shall show in Book III. that, with a given rate of surplus value, we
may have any number of rates of profit, and that various rates of
surplus value may, under given conditions, express themselves in a
single rate of profit.” (p 491)
Labels:
Capitalism,
Marxist Economic Theory
Wednesday, 26 December 2012
Equivalent Form of Value
The Value of a commodity can be expressed in a certain quantity of some other Use Value. This quantity is the Equivalent Form of the commodity's Value. For example, the Value of 1 metre of linen can be expressed as 10 kilos of sugar. 10 kilos of sugar is the Equivalent Form of the Value of 1 metre of linen.
If this expression is turned around, we can express the Value of sugar as a certain quantity of the other Use Value, Linen. Then we would have 10 kilos of sugar expressed as 1 metre of linen. Then 1 metre of linen is the Equivalent Form of Value of 10 kilos of sugar. Exchange Value can only be expressed as a certain quantity of some other Use Value, whilst Value itself can be expressed as a certain quantity of Abstract Labour Time.
Where some commodity is separated off from other commodities, in order to act as an Equivalent Form of Value, against which all other commodities can be measured, this Universal Equivalent Form of Value can act as a money commodity.
For a fuller discussion see Capital I, Chapter 1 - Part 4
Labels:
Marxist Economic Theory
Metamorphosis
Marx uses the term metamorphosis, for example in relation to the exchange of commodities for money in order to emphasise that both sides of this exchange have an inner connectedness. It is not two totally distinct things that simply exchange places, but a process by which one becomes the other and vice versa.
The butterfly has an innner connectedness with the caterpillar. It does not simply take the place of the caterpillar but emerges from it. The commodity can only be exchanged for money because both have an inner connectedness, both are expressions of Exchange Value and of Use Value, but each only has the form of one of these at any one time. It is for that reason that both contain the other within it, just as the butterfly contains the caterpillar within it, that enables one to become the other.
The commodity is Exchange Value for its owner, but Use Value for its potential buyer. Likewise, Money is Exchange Value for its owner but Use Value for the seller who obtains it in exchange for their commodity (its usefulness is that it can be used to purchase other commodities). In the process of exchange one metamorphoses into the other.
This concept of metamorphosis is not restricted to the exchange of commodities. Dialectics takes as its starting point the nature of reality as based on continuous change. Change as a continuous process itself involves the idea that the present is pregnant with the future i.e. the future is not some discrete period of time that simply takes the place of the present, but is itself inextricably bound up and connected to the present. The future emerges out of the present.
The butterfly has an innner connectedness with the caterpillar. It does not simply take the place of the caterpillar but emerges from it. The commodity can only be exchanged for money because both have an inner connectedness, both are expressions of Exchange Value and of Use Value, but each only has the form of one of these at any one time. It is for that reason that both contain the other within it, just as the butterfly contains the caterpillar within it, that enables one to become the other.
The commodity is Exchange Value for its owner, but Use Value for its potential buyer. Likewise, Money is Exchange Value for its owner but Use Value for the seller who obtains it in exchange for their commodity (its usefulness is that it can be used to purchase other commodities). In the process of exchange one metamorphoses into the other.
This concept of metamorphosis is not restricted to the exchange of commodities. Dialectics takes as its starting point the nature of reality as based on continuous change. Change as a continuous process itself involves the idea that the present is pregnant with the future i.e. the future is not some discrete period of time that simply takes the place of the present, but is itself inextricably bound up and connected to the present. The future emerges out of the present.
Labels:
Marxism
Socially Necessary Labour
Summary
- Socially necessary labour-time is the amount of labour-time required, on average, to produce a commodity.
- This has to be understood in two contexts, a narrow context and a wider context.
- The narrow context is that each producer of the commodity is forced, by competition, to always produce by the most efficient means, so that they use no more labour-time than is necessary to produce the commodity. Each individual producer produces under different conditions of production, so that each requires more or less labour-time than other producers to produce a given amount of output. In other words, the individual value of the output of each producer differs. The average amount of labour-time required by all producers of a particular commodity, thereby, determines the socially necessary labour-time. Similarly, the average derived from aggregating all of the individual values of output for the different producers, gives the market value of the total output. Those producers that produce at an individual value below the market value make surplus profits, and those that produce at an individual value above market value, make below average profit.
- The wider context is that the labour-time expended on the total production of a commodity, which thereby determines the market value of the commodity, must not result in a greater supply of the commodity than the demand for the commodity at that market value. If the supply exceeds the demand, at the market value, then labour has been expended in production that was not socially necessary, because a product, and thereby a commodity, only has value if it is a use value. A commodity for which there is no demand is not a use value, and so has no value, and the labour expended was not socially necessary. For example, if 1000 units of commodity A are produced, and the unit market value of these units is £1, if, at a price of £1, there is only demand for 800 units, then 20% of the labour-time expended was not socially necessary. It is as though the value of the 1000 units was only £800, so that the unit value is only £0.80. To sell all 1,000 units, the price per unit has to fall to £0.80.
~~~~~~~~~
When Marx talks about Labour being "Socially Necessary" he does so in a specific sense. From the perspective of some rational society there are many types of labour, which today not only exist, but which are highly remunerative, that would not be needed. In fact, Joseph Schumpeter pointed out that this was one way in which Socialism would be economically more efficient than Capitalism. For example, today, huge sums are spent on marketing and advertising. The labour time spent on these activities is not designed to provide consumers with information to enable them to make rational choices about commodities, but is instead designed simply to persuade consumers to buy this product rather than some other product, to depict some qualitative difference between branded products that does not really exist, and to ensure that commodities produced by large producers, as part of a large scale long term production plan, find a market.
A society that geared its production to meet consumer needs would have no need of such wasteful and useless expenditure of resources. Similarly, huge sums are spent on litigation involving very highly paid lawyers, in respect mostly of issues surrounding disputes over property and contracts. A cooperative society would have no need of such expensive means of resolving conflicts where they arose, and the more property was collectively owned, the less such conflicts would arise. Adam Smith and other Classical economists themselves were at great pains to describe the huge waste of resources that was represented by useless functionaries such as the clergy, and the sustenance of whom, drained society's resources that could be better spent. Similar huge sums are wasted on other useless activities such as the maintenance of the Monarchy and its entourage, as well as the huge sums required to maintain a massive capitalist state apparatus, and the machinery of government. All of these wasteful expenditures of labour-time would be ended by a rational cooperative society.
However, within the context of a commodity producing society all of these activities can be considered socially necessary expenditures of labour-time. All that is required within this restricted meaning is that someone is prepared to buy the product of this labour as a commodity. The labour-time expended by an advertising specialist, or a contract lawyer is socially necessary provided some capitalist is prepared to buy it. Conversely, an expenditure of labour-time that might be considered socially necessary under a rational cooperative society, may not be so in a commodity producing society. For example, the former might see the expenditure of labour-time by a surgeon as socially necessary, and yet a commodity producing society might limit how much labour-time is devoted to it, because there is insufficient effective demand for it.
Because capitalism operates on the basis of producing first, and seeking a market for what has been produced afterwards, the potential for the effective demand being less than what has been produced is always present. In other words, labour-time has been expended that was not needed. It was not socially necessary labour-time. Marx's definition of socially necessary here is considered only in the context of a commodity producing and exchanging economy, just as with his definition of productive labour, it is delineated within the context of an analysis of capitalism, and consequently in terms of what is productive of surplus value, and the accumulation, thereby of capital.
Taking this understanding of the overall context in which Marx refers to socially necessary labour, it also falls under two headings, a narrow description and a broader description.
The Narrow Description
This assumes that everything produced is also demanded at its market value. Provided this is the case, then competition forces each producer to produce by the most efficient means possible for them. For example, its possible to produce nails from gold, but there is no reason to use gold for this purpose, as iron or some other cheaper metal will suffice at least as good, for the purpose. Using gold would not be a use of only socially necessary labour, because the labour used in producing the gold is not necessary for the purpose of producing nails. Producers of nails will seek to use the cheapest metal available that provides the utility required from a nail. In the process, this, in itself, via competition, drives the producers of iron, steel, zinc etc. to produce by the most efficient means possible so as to maximise their market share against their competitors in selling material to nail makers.
In this way, competition drives down the labour-time required for the materials used in nail making, as well as that required to produce nail making machinery, factories in which nail-making is to be undertaken and so on. So, it reduces the labour-time required to produce the constant capital consumed in nail making. The nail makers themselves also seek to minimise their own use of living labour in the production process. They seek to utilise the division of labour, to enjoy the benefits of cooperative labour, to produce on the largest scale their capital permits, so as to obtain the economies of scale, and they seek to use the latest technology so as to raise the productivity of their own workers.
Taking all this into consideration, however, each producer of nails will produce any given quantity of nails using different amounts of labour-time, because some producers will be more efficient than others, some will have various advantages than enable them to be more productive and so on. A producer close to suppliers of iron, for example, will be able to produce at a lower cost, because they will not have to bear the cost of having raw material shipped over long distances to them. Producers in an area with a history of nail-making will benefit from the fact that the workers in the area will have a history of nail production that leads to them being more adept in that line of production, the skills, thereby, being handed down from one generation to the next. Some producers may have access to cheap energy supplies to drive machinery, some may simply have more astute managers who are able to acquire cheaper materials, or organise production more effectively.
For all these reasons, each producer will require more or less labour-time to produce a given quantity of nails. Put another way, the individual value of the output of each producer will differ. But, each producer will produce as efficiently as their available capital, and the given material conditions allow them to do. So long as there is a demand for the output of all these producers, then each producer will continue in business. If the labour-time required by all these producers is aggregated, and divided across their total output, then this gives the average socially necessary labour-time required for this output. Measured across the total output it gives the market value of each unit of that output, which is, thereby, also the aggregate of the individual values of output for each producer.
But, because each producer produces output with a different individual value to its competitors, those producers that produce with a lower individual value than the market value will obtain surplus profits, and vice versa. In other words, those producers that use less social labour in their production than the average socially necessary labour, in that line of production, will make surplus profits, and this, in itself, acts as a spur for each producer to reduce the labour-time required for their own production.
The Broader Description
But socially necessary labour-time has to be considered in a broader definition. A use value is only a use value if someone has a use for it. Similarly, a product is only a product if it is a use value, and is the product of labour. A product only has value because it is a use value and is the product of labour. A commodity is a product that has been produced for the specific purpose of sale, and likewise, therefore, a commodity only has value, if it is both the product of labour, and is a use value. But, a commodity is also only a use value, if someone wants to buy it, at its market value. For commodity production and exchange, demand is only ever effective demand, i.e. demand backed by both a willingness and ability to buy at the market value.
Commodities, therefore, may be produced by the most efficient means possible at the time, and yet the labour used in their production may not be socially necessary if there is no effective demand for them, or for all of them. I might produce the cheapest car possible, using the most efficient methods possible, but if no one likes the car, and wants to buy it, the labour used in its production, both the labour used to build the car, plus the labour used to produce the materials consumed in its production etc., was not socially necessary. Similarly, if 1000 units of commodity A are produced, using the most efficient means possible, which results in a market value of £1 per unit, if there is only demand for 800 units, at a price of £1 per unit, then the labour expended in producing the 200 units not demanded was not socially necessary. It is, then, as though the labour expended on producing these surplus 200 units did not exist, so that the value of the 1000 units falls to just £0.80 per unit.
At this price, output will have to be cut back, and normally this would occur by the least efficient producer going out of business. As a result of them no longer producing, the average socially necessary labour-time required for production, and, thereby, the market value itself, falls.
Labels:
Marxist Economic Theory
Primary Accumulation
Primary Accumulation is the process Marx describes by which capital is initially formed. It comprises a number of elements. Firstly, before Capitalism proper arises, "capital" is accumulated in the form of Money Capital and Merchant Capital. Using Marx's definition of what Capital is - a social relation based on Capital and Wage Labour, where these two appear as two sides of the same coin - these two types of "capital" are not capital at all.
Capital can only exist as one part of a social relation with wage labour. Wage Labour creates surplus value, which is then accumulated to form new capital. But, neither Money Capital, nor Merchant Capital employ Wage Labour to create Surplus Value. In their original form both these types of "capital" obtain a profit by a process of unequal exchange. The Money Capitalist lends out money, and receives back a larger sum of money, which includes a payment of interest. The Merchant Capitalist buys commodities from a producer, at a price below their exchange value, and sells them at a price at or even above their exchange value. The value of commodities always includes an amount of surplus value, because the commodity producer undertakes labour over and above necessary labour, in producing them. Its out of this surplus value that the interest and commercial profit is appropriated, along with rent, and taxes. In fact, Marx says that the dominance of these "antediluvian forms" of capital precludes the existence of capitalism, even though they form a necessary element of its development.
That is because these forms are one means by which large hoards of money can be accumulated, which, in turn, can be turned into capital i.e. can be used to employ Wage Labour. That is one form in which Primary Accumulation can occur. Another form is that some of those forces that become the Merchant or Money Capitalists, can themselves accumulate hoards of money - perhaps to set up in these businesses - by other activities. So, for example, many merchants began as pirates and privateers, often with Royal approval for their activities. People like Drake and Raleigh, and their Spanish and other European counterparts, were pirates who both stole booty from ships on the high seas, as well as acquiring, by various means, commodities from the Americas and elsewhere that could be sold back in Europe at high prices.
One of these commodities was, of course, slaves. One of the main sources of Primary Accumulation in Britain, was indeed the so called Triangle Trade, whereby British merchant ships would pick up slaves from Africa, deposit them in the Caribbean, where they were set to work, by British Landlords, who had transferred their feudal activities abroad, producing sugar and other high value crops, which the merchant ships then brought back to Liverpool, where they were sold. This was the basis of the Tate and Lyle Sugar Empire. But, the huge funds derived from this trade also provided the initial Capital for the establishment of most of Britain's commercial banks.
The Merchant Capitalists applied the same principles in Britain, buying from British independent producers commodities below their value, and selling those commodities in nearby markets at prices above their values. It was a simple step from this process to provide those producers with the materials required for their production, and then to bring those producers together in a manufactory.
In addition to this process, however, as Marx points out, many of the actual industrial capitalists, the capitalists proper, were themselves small independent producers, like Wedgwood, who accumulated capital by saving from the surplus value they produced, i.e. the labour undertaken in excess of necessary labour. Marx notes that, in this initial period, these industrial capitalists were indistinguishable from their workers. If anything they may have appeared more miserable, precisely because they were saving a proportion of their revenue rather than consuming it.
However, the capital created by this primary accumulation rapidly becomes something of an anomaly, and irrelevant. Once, this capital is put into operation, it extracts surplus value from the workers employed, which is then accumulated, as new capital. Very quickly, it is this capital created from the exploitation of the workers, from their unpaid labour, which constitutes the vast bulk of capital employed. On this basis, the surplus value created also rises exponentially so that the capitalists are able both to accumulate further capital from it, and to increase their own unproductive consumption to heights never before seen in history.
The Freedom of Reason
A Critique of R.M. Hare’s “Freedom and Reason”
Descriptive Meaning
Hare wants to argue
that words and judgements share “descriptive meaning”. By this
he wants to make the following logical argument. If I call something
“red” then I am forced to describe everything else with the same
essential properties, which cause me to describe this object as
“red”, “like in the relevant respects” to use Hare’s
phrase, as also being “red”. Similarly, if I describe something
as “good” the “relevant respects” which cause me to make this
judgement must, if they occur in some other instance, cause me to
conclude that this other is also “good”. This is the basis of
“universalisability”. Hare makes clear that in defining
“descriptive meaning” he is not talking about things being
“exactly like” each other because they never are, and this would,
in any case, mean that such “descriptive meaning” and, by
implication, moral rules were trivial.
But, Hare seems unaware
that his looser “like in the relevant respects” suffers
essentially the same problem. It is not just that different people
will see red differently, which Hare recognises, but that the change
from being red to orange is not a discrete but a continuous one. At
some point red stops being red and starts being orange, and yet
identifying this point is in fact impossible, because at this point
red is both red and orange, just as at the point of tangency a circle
is both flat, and not flat. Hare is unable to come to terms with
this because his logic is based on the syllogistic logic of Aristotle
which denies such contradictions. At these inflexion points
syllogistic logic breaks down, and dialectics takes over.
For the same individual
if the length of light waves is gradually changed then red becomes
orange. Through a whole range the “relevant respects” allow him
to continue to describe every hue he sees as “red”, but at some
point he will describe the colour not as “red” but “orange”.
It will always be possible to make smaller and smaller adjustments to
the wavelength such that our individual will change his description
between “red” and “orange”, and may even over very small time
periods describe the same frequency at one time as “red” and at
another as “orange”. Nor is this problem resolved by describing
“orange” as a type of “red”, as Hare does with “Scarlet”
etc., because applying the same process we would end up through
“yellow” and “green” to “blue”, thereby arriving at the
ridiculous conclusion of describing “blue” as a variant of “red”.
Blue can, of course be described as a variant of red only in the
sense that red is a variant of blue i.e. they are both colours.
Non-Triviality
But it is precisely at
the inflexion points that the importance and non-triviality exist.
If we transfer the issue over to the real purpose of Hare’s concern
– morals – then a thesis which only allows the development of
rules for situations which are as clear-cut as the difference between
“red” and “blue” is trivial indeed. The non-triviality is to
provide a basis for those situations which are not clear-cut. To
transfer the argument used above to a moral dilemma let us try to put
this into the kind of formulation that Hare proposes.
“It is good to kill
someone if this is done as an act of self-defence of another innocent
human being.”
There may be many
clear-cut instances where this judgement is true. A policeman shoots
a known serial killer and child molester holding a knife at a young
child’s throat, for instance. Though even here the policeman
cannot be sure the individual would actually kill the child. But
there may be many gradations of this which possess the “like in the
relevant respects”, but which may cause a different course of
action. For example, I hear X in the pub say “I am going to kill
Y.” Few people would say this justified me in killing X in order
to save Y’s life. For one thing I would want to know whether X was
speaking literally, what was the seriousness of his intent?
Moreover, such a situation lacks immediacy. Other courses of action
are open such as warning Y, informing the police etc.
The Truth Is Always Concrete
Lenin summed up the basis of dialectics in the phrase "The truth is always concrete." |
But, suppose I know
that X has some reason to threaten Y, and Y is about to come into the
pub? Still there may be other options rather than me killing X.
Suppose Y comes into the pub, and I see X pull a gun out of a bag
under the table? But, still I don’t know if this is a real gun, if
it is loaded, if X really does intend to kill Y or just scare him.
Suppose, X attracts Y’s attention by firing into the ceiling
causing plaster to fall and shouting out to him in abusive terms. I
now know that the gun is real and had at least one bullet. Yet Y may
escape, X might not be a good shot, he could miss etc. etc. Would I
be entitled to shoot him if I had my own gun? Suppose I knew that X
was a crack shot in the army and unlikely to miss, and had killed
before, would I be acting morally if I shot him then?
Only by using rules
which are completely prescriptive could these questions be resolved,
but with such a level of prescription rather than a universal rule we
have a particular rule rather than a universal one. In the end,
Hare’s formulation comes down to what he wanted to avoid by trying
to escape describing situations as exactly the same. “Like in the
relevant respects” merely allows us to provide universal rules for
clear-cut instances i.e. it becomes trivial, whereas the more tricky
instances where philosophical analysis should be most important
demonstrates the impotence of Hare’s approach.
Hare argues that what
is important about words like “good” is their prescriptive
meaning. He contrasts this with other moral words like
“industrious”. For “industrious” its descriptive meaning is
primary and its prescriptive meaning secondary. A society may see
“industriousness” not as a moral positive, but as a negative.
Its descriptive meaning would remain the same, but its prescriptive
meaning i.e. as a recommended action would have changed. However,
Hare says, if we considered a man “good” because he was
industrious the change in the prescriptive meaning of industrious
does not mean we no longer consider the man “good”. There may be
other reasons for calling him “good”. If the descriptive meaning
of “good” changes to no longer include industrious as one of its
attributes, one of the “relevant respects” which cause us to
describe someone as “good”, this does not change the prescriptive
meaning of “good”. In other words Hare wants to set aside words
like “good” from other words like “industrious” which may
form attributes of what constitutes “good”. "Good" will then
always have a prescriptive meaning which is positive, however much
its descriptive meaning changes.
But this is the problem
with language. For example, it became part of the language of youth
to refer to people/things positively as “bad”, as in “that
brother is bad”, or “that is one bad piece of music”. Here the
meaning of “bad” is positive not negative, and to give the
converse of this it is often that people use the term “do-gooder”
not in a prescriptively positive but negative sense.
Hare also uses the
example of the word “nigger” to show that this could not be used
if one wanted to speak to a black person as an equal. Yet it is
perhaps an indication of the increased confidence of black people
that they now refer to each other in those terms without any sense of
shame.
Hare argues that
differences of opinion over descriptive meaning can be resolved by
agreeing a definition whereas such differences in relation to value
terms cannot. He uses the example of cutting down trees, and the
question of what constitutes a tree rather than a bush. This would
appear straightforward. But as the line he draws demonstrates it is
not so straightforward. He suggests it does not matter if we call
the thing in question a tree or a bush provided we agree to cut down
everything under 15 feet with the lowest branch at least 3 feet from
the ground. Yet this would include young trees, which are not
bushes. In fact a far more detailed description is required to
distinguish trees from bushes, and there is no reason why two
individuals should agree to every aspect of these details. If the
requirement is to cut down every bush then unless an agreement on
what constitutes a bush can be reached then an agreed course of
action cannot follow. To simply say cut down everything below 15
feet etc. is to change the terms of the problem, not to resolve the
problem.
Universality
Hare sets out a
definition of “Universality” which is different from Kant's Categorical Imperative, although later on the difference is somewhat
fudged in his application of “Universality”. The CI says I can
only judge a decision to be moral if I could will such an act to be
adopted by everyone. Hare’s “Universality”, however, only
requires that the act be capable of being adopted by people in the
same situation, or “relevantly similar circumstances” as Hare
puts it. It is in the definition of what constitutes “relevantly
similar circumstances” that the blurring occurs later on. So, for
example, suppose I am poor. I ask myself “Is it moral to steal
from the rich?" (I might use Hare’s method of defining rich used in
the example of the bush and the trees i.e. wealth above a certain
amount). I think yes. Then I ask is this universalisable to others
in the same position? Again I think yes, because, being poor, I am
in no danger of willing an act of theft against myself to be moral.
Under, Hare’s approach then it is quite logical for the poor to
consider stealing from the rich to be moral. This is not the case
with the CI because it is not limited to people in the same position.
I would have to ask is it possible for everyone to adopt this rule
and it would be clear that the rich would have no reason to adopt it.
Hare faced with the contradiction which his formulation creates in
practice, changes the formulation so that instead of the individual
asking could he accept such a rule being adopted by others in the
same situation he changes the test so that the individual is asked to
step outside reality, and to put himself in the position of someone
who might suffer from the application of the rule, in other words
someone not in the same position. But this effectively removes the
difference with the CI.
Petit-Bourgeois Morality
Hare gives the example
of someone being forced to shore in a boat to distinguish the
question “Shall I be forced on to shore?” as being really “Will
I be forced on to shore” rather than a request for guidance. From
this he gives an example of an honest and dishonest cashier. The
dishonest cashier suggests to the other he take money for his
holidays. Hare argues that although neuroscience might show that
such a person would never commit such an act they would still ask the
question, and their action is still a moral act resulting from asking
the question. But does this hold in reverse. If neuroscience shows
the dishonest cashier will inevitably take the money can we say they
would even ask the question. If I am hungry and have appetising food
placed in front of me, I do not ask myself the question “Shall I
eat”, I just eat. If the dishonest cashier is physically
conditioned, either by nature or by nurture to take what they need
then if they need money and see the opportunity to take some, why
would they ask whether or not they should? Hare also says that
scientific advancement showing that people are conditioned to act in
a particular way does not mean we can then abstain from making moral
judgements of people’s actions. But either this is sterile or
contradicts Hare’s thesis. If “universal” only means other
people in the same condition and circumstances then how can I judge
whether someone else acted morally. I can ask myself whether I would
have acted as they did knowing my condition and circumstance, but
this tells me nothing about the morality of their
action because their position and circumstance is not mine.
The rules of all games favour the strengths of some players as against the weaknesses of others. The important question is, "Who creates the rules?" |
Hare argues that ethics
is morally neutral. He makes a parallel with the rules of games,
arguing that the rules of a game are neutral between the players.
But this is clearly false. If I know the strengths and weaknesses of
the players, then it is a simple matter to construct rules, which
favour the strengths of one player and diminish the chances of the
other. A moral equivalent might be to say that no one should steal.
Is such a rule neutral? No. If you are rich you have not the same
need to steal as someone poor. The important question here then is
who makes the rules. It is invariably the most powerful, wealthy and
privileged, and it is not surprising then that the rules they make,
whilst masquerading as neutral, in fact are designed to ensure their
supremacy, power, wealth and privilege is maintained.
Hare’s version of
“universalisable” as compared with Kant’s, however, does
provide the freedom for those not part of this dominant group to
define their own morality in contrast to it. Because Hare’s
“universalisable” is limited to those in similar circumstances
not to everyone. So the working class could, for instance, decide
its members were all in the same circumstance and find it morally
positive to deprive the capitalists of their property. As such a
decision for each member of the working class only has to pass the
test “could this decision be universalisable to others in the same
position i.e. other workers” then this meets Hare’s criterion.
As this results in conclusions which infringe Hare’s Liberal
ideology he is forced in practice to abandon this formulation later
on without recognising he has done so.
Morality - Uncomfortable Conclusions
Hare then gives an
example of how his formulation could be applied. He gives the
example of someone (B) owed money by (A) who asks himself whether A
should be put in gaol. The example seems to fail for a number of
reasons, some of which Hare admits. Hare suggests that in deciding
the person should consider his position if he owed a third person (C)
money, and whether his rule would then justify this third person
having him gaoled. Hare argues that as in general people do not want
to be put in gaol he would not wish C to do this to him, and
therefore could not adopt it as a principle in relation to A. But as
Hare recognises B could feel that C should indeed put him in prison
even though he would lose out from this. Secondly, the “in similar
circumstances” here does not explore what else might need to be
known about A, B and C. For instance, A might be rich and capable of
paying B but refuses. B might be poor and only owes C because A has
not paid him. The sensible course then might be for B and C to
combine and threaten A with gaol unless he paid up because
essentially A owes both B and C.
This is the problem
with the concept of “universalisable”. Nearly every situation is
different. In this latter case the shared interest of both B and C
puts them both in a class as against A, but leads B to conclude
morally that A should go to gaol, but also to conclude that C should
not send him to gaol, because the situation is different. Hare’s
reasoning seems to result in strange conclusions, which he finds
himself having to go into contortions later on to resolve. If we
change the above example this can be demonstrated. B considers
whether A should be punished for committing murder. He concludes
that as he would not want to be punished if he committed murder then
A should face no sanction!! Hare retorts in the case of B arguing
for imprisonment on the basis of his principled belief in the
sanctity of property and contracts that such a position could be
defended if he can show that laxity of enforcement would have serious
consequences for society. But again this is to assume that all
members of society have the same interests and this is a false
assumption. In a society made up of debtors and creditors the
creditors would no doubt agree with B’s principled stand, but it is
unlikely the debtors would share it. The issue then resolves not
into questions of freedom or reason, but of power and control, of who
sets the rules.
Hare retorts on the
question of there being differences between A and B’s cases that
first of all he has hypothesised the case away. But rules including
moral rules are only useful if they deal with actual reality rather
than hypothesised fantasy. If in reality the hypothetical
equivalence of A, B and C cannot exist (and it cannot) then rules
based on that equality are at best useless, and at worst misleading.
The appeal to “universalisability” that Hare uses as his second
response does not work either. If I am poor and always expect to be
poor there is little point in asking me to put myself in the place of
the rich. If I am a white, Aryan Nazi, there is little point in
asking me to put myself in the place of the Jew. Whilst I might, and
do, abhor the moral decisions the Nazi arrives at I cannot deny using
Hare’s own method of developing moral rules the Nazi’s are as
justified as anyone else’s. He examines the “facts” as he sees
them, and asks “Could others in the same position as me (i.e.
white, Aryan, Nazis) arrive at the same decisions", and concludes
“Yes”.
In the end, Hare's Moral rules come down to the same presentation of the ideas and interests of the petit-bourgeois, as universal, as that of Bentham. |
But it is here that
Hare moves away from his original formulation when confronted with
this result, effectively adopting the Kantian position. He no longer
sees “universalisability” as the ability to view things from the
actual position of the given real individual, and all others in the
same position, but from the standpoint of some non-existent, abstract
individual. Once again we are led into making moral rules not based
on reality, but fantastic hypotheticals. The consequence is that
instead of Hare’s philosophy providing a basis for understanding
human behaviour and morals it does the opposite. He is left
describing people like the Nazis as fanatics because although the
true Nazi is untouched by Hare’s theory, in order to justify the
rationality of his moral rules i.e. he has to say “if I were a Jew
I would want to be killed and persecuted”, this belief in itself
must be seen as so irrational that only a few could hold it
consistently. But it is only by understanding that given the
circumstances Nazis can view their morality, ideas and actions as
rational that we can understand the development of those ideas. On
Hare’s philosophy the development of such forces and ideas is
inexplicable other than by labelling them as fanatical. The converse
of this of course is that there is some set of rational ideas and
morals that is “universalisable” to everyone, and effectively
Hare sees these as being those that come under the heading of
“Liberalism”.
Fanaticism and Rationality
Hare goes on to phrase
the question as “What do you say in a hypothetical case in which
you are in your victim’s position?” If we put this back to the
example I gave earlier where A is a murderer, B faces the question
“should I punish A?” If B puts himself in the hypothetical
situation of being a murderer would he want to be punished? The
question is in many ways ludicrous because B can never know what he
would feel unless he were actually in that position. But, were B to
say “Yes, I should be punished”, would we want to call him a
fanatic. But for the Nazi with a deep seated hatred of Jews based on
what they believe to be facts, the idea that as a race they were
responsible for the death of Christ, that they are sub-human and all
the other nonsense, it is quite logical for such a Nazi to say “If
I were one of these people I would expect to be punished”, just as
it is logical for most humans to say they would expect to be punished
if they were a murderer.
Who were the real fanatics? The Spanish Inquisition or the heretics they persecuted? |
Hare’s problem is
that he wants to use his own perceptions and prejudices to define
what is rational for everyone else. For although, he says there is
no logical reason for someone not to hold these views he labels those
that do “fanatics” and bases this on the idea that those that
hold them are a minority. But by this token if they were a majority
then the minority that didn’t hold them would be fanatics. This
seems to be moral decision making by populism. A similar approach is
taken when Hare retorts to the issue of criminal behaviour. He says
that a judge when faced with the question “would I like to be put
into prison were I the criminal” has to take into consideration the
interests of society. Besides the fact that this is removed from
Hare’s original methodology of how to decide on moral issues it
does not seem to provide the solution he requires. As a member of
society and moral individual doesn’t the creditor take this into
account too, indeed doesn’t the Nazi take into account what he sees
as the interest of society. Moreover, the quantity of people
involved doesn’t logically seem to change the end decision. If all
individuals were asked the question “would you like to be put in
prison?” according to Hare’s version of what a rational response
would be unless they were fanatics the answer would be “No.” And
if as Hare argues the judge is there to represent the community his
response should also be that the criminal should not be imprisoned
otherwise his view is contrary to the view of society.
Hare’s argument that
the judge can say to the criminal “I find it easier to adopt the
maxim ‘thieves should be put in prison’” is a cop-out because
it is answering a different moral question than the one he has posed.
All he has demonstrated is that different moral rules conflict with
each other. Suppose I adopt a moral rule “People ought not commit
murder”. This does not tell me what the consequence should be if
someone does commit murder. If I have another moral rule that says
“Murderer’s should not be punished” based on my own aversion to
punishment then I am left merely with the fact that in committing
murder they act immorally but cannot punish them without acting
immorally myself. If I then act immorally and punish them, who
punishes me, and so on.
Moreover, the argument
Hare uses to arrive at this new maxim is very dangerous. He says the
judge might reason that unless the criminal is punished he might rob
others, or other people might follow his example and rob. If we then
use these two arguments the judge might be asked “Would you like to
be punished for things you have not yet done?” Or, “Would you
like to be punished for things done by other people?” This kind of
argument would lead to all kinds of arbitrary punishment.
Hare gives another
example using a chocolate bar. He says if three equal people come to
share a chocolate bar they can morally agree to have a third each.
If one does not like chocolate they can reach a universal decision
that those that don’t like chocolate should not be given any, and
consequently it be divided into two. But the third party could
equally logically come to the conclusion that no one should have any.
They have nothing to gain by the first decision, and might even feel
deprived as a result of it. They may feel better with the second
decision though the other two will likely disagree. The decision of
both groups is universal only to its own group.
Utility
Hare goes on in some
detail in respect of utilitarian methods of arriving at moral
decisions. He says he has some sympathy with the “rule-utilitarian”
system modified by particular instances to arrive at less general
rules. I have little to say here other than that “utility” as a
concept in morals suffers the same problems it does in economics i.e.
it is unmeasurable. It is, therefore, impossible to maximise because
to do so requires the ability to compare one quantity of utility with
another. Like its economic counterpart utility in this context is
fine for those sitting in ivory towers developing theories based on
fantastic hypotheticals but has no grounding in reality.
Hare then moves on to a
discussion of aesthetics, which takes us back to the beginning of the
discussion and the issue of “like in the relevant respects”.
Hare uses the example of Siamese cats to say that if we describe one
as “beautiful” then we are compelled to say that all others
“alike in the relevant respects” are also beautiful. But there
is a logical problem here similar to that encountered at the
beginning. If I take two cats, not identical but “alike in the
relevant respects” then if I call the first beautiful then I will
call the second beautiful too. But suppose I introduce a third cat,
which is like the second in all the relevant respects but less like
the first than the second. As I introduce further cats they may be
almost identical to the one before it but less and less like the
first. The more cats we introduce the less reason we have to call
these cats beautiful just because that was how we categorised the
first. Quantity has been transformed into quality. The only way to
avoid this is to give the words “alike in the relevant respects”
the meaning “identical”, but that is what Hare wants to avoid
because he knows that such identity does not exist.
Morality - Idealism v Materialism
Hare wants to argue
that conflicts of interest are resolvable through negotiation and
bargaining whereas conflicts of ideals are not. But this is somewhat
facile. If there is a fundamental conflict of interest e.g. between
workers and capitalists a modus vivendi may be reached based on
bargaining as happens with Trade Unions, but this does not resolve
the conflict which continues to exist and to manifest itself over and
over until such time as the basis of the conflict is removed. The
same is true of Hare’s example of World War II which he wrongly
ascribes as being a conflict of ideals between Nazism and Liberalism.
Such a description is clearly false when one considers that not only
did liberal democracy fail to counter fascism in Italy during the
1920’s or in Germany in the 1930’s, but leading representatives
of Liberal democracy openly welcomed it. And during the Spanish
Civil War democracy failed to come to the support of those fighting
fascism even with such modest means as the supply of arms. The real
basis of the war was not a conflict of ideals, but was precisely a
conflict of economic interest. Both groups had no difficulty in
universalising their own respective economic interest into a moral
justification of their actions. Moreover, far from the
intractability of the Nazis ideals being a barrier to resolution with
the Liberal ideals in Britain and the US, it did not prevent the US
from staying out of the war until it was half way through, nor of
many in the US believing then and afterwards that they should have
been fighting on the other side, nor indeed of America and Britain
supporting regimes with similar ideals both then and since.
Contrary to Hare’s
assertion, experience particularly since WWII has been that
conflicting ideals are negotiable in terms of which states to support
and deal with provided that it is to the end of promoting economic or
other strategic interest. This was demonstrably true of the US
during WWII, which, despite the fact of knowing exactly what ideals
the Nazis had and how they were treating Jews, continued to trade
with them, US companies continued to operate in Germany including
those being used to manufacture weapons used against Jews and British
soldiers. The US did not have the same economic conflict with
Germany that Britain did. The US had an economic conflict with
Japan, with whom it went to war, thus bringing it into war against
Germany as Japan’s ally.
But it is in the
question of ideals that Hare needed to make the change in the way he
defines “universalisable”. Originally, his definition was “could
other people like me in the relevant respects make the same decision
on questions like this one.” On this basis the Nazis logic does
not require resort to “ideals” but merely to imagine that other
Nazis can come to the same conclusion. To ask him to put himself in
the place of the Jew as Hare now requires him to do is to ask him to
put himself in the place of someone different to him “in the
relevant respects” and thereby to contradict the original
formulation.
Hare then uses a
different argument based upon his discussion of aesthetics. He
argues that just because I hate a piece of music does not mean I have
a moral duty to disrupt its performance. Similarly, the Nazis hatred
of Jews does not mean they have a moral duty to persecute them. But
this is a straw man. Changing the terms of this argument defeats it.
If instead of a piece of music I place the smallpox bacteria then my
hatred of it, and concern for its effects on others would logically
lead me to believe I should act on this and try to eradicate it.
However perverse and disgusting, the Nazis viewed the Jews almost
exactly in this light so Hare’s argument does not seem to apply.
He proposes a trick to
expose the Nazis illogicality or fanaticism. He proposes making the
Nazi believe that he is a Jew, and seeing if his opinion then
changes. If it does then his moral rule is illogical, if it does not
then he is a fanatic. A bit like the old test for witches by
drowning them. If they didn’t drown they were a witch, if they did
they were not. But this trick fails Hare’s original formulation of
“like in the relevant respects”. If we go back to Hare’s
original discussion about red, and what is necessary for something to
be called red, we could put red in the place of Nazi and see that the
condition is not met. If a condition of redness is not being blue,
and a condition of being a Nazi is not being a Jew (at least in the
sense of being a 1930’s German Nazi) then it is clear that a
significant failure of Hare’s argument arises here. Hare proceeded
to say that everything else containing the essential elements of
“red” lead us to say that everything else containing these must
be red, and that we are committed to saying so. In order for
universalisability to happen it is necessary that everyone who is
like me “in the relevant respects” should be able to come to the
same conclusion that this is red. Presumably a blind person could
not because they are not like me.
But as soon as I trick
the Nazi into believing he is a Jew “the relevant respects” of
what made him a Nazi have changed. He is now free to assess his new
position and to adopt a new set of rules appropriate to it. If we
ask the Nazi then to apply Hare’s rule he says “I am a Nazi, I
should exterminate Jews, can I universalise this rule by saying
anyone else in similar circumstances i.e. being a Nazi should act the
same?” He says “Yes.” Once he no longer believes himself to
be a Nazi because of being a Jew this link to others being “in
relevantly similar circumstances” is broken.
The argument Hare then
uses about people being very rare who would want to be killed
themselves e.g. if they were themselves a Jew is weak. Suppose I ask
myself “Were I to contract an awful infectious disease and might
infect my family causing a horrible death, and the only way to avoid
this would be to be killed and have my body burned, should I do
this?” The fact that the prospect is remote might help me to
assent to such a principle, but there are many who would do so, and
be considered very moral for it. As the Nazi feels the same way
about the Jew it is not unrealistic to believe that such a principle
would be rational. It does not matter that the basis on which the
Nazi bases his evaluation is a gross perversion of truth, because
people can only be requested to base their decisions on the basis of
the facts as they perceive them. Given that there are not a few
supposedly reputable psychologists in the liberal democracies who
over the years have presented papers supposedly showing that black
people, or working class people have lower IQ’s, it is not
surprising that people can be convinced of such ideas.
If we then go back to
Hare’s trick then if the Nazi changed his mind when made to believe
that he was a Jew this could be interpreted as moral weakness, just
as the man who agrees to the principle he should be sacrificed rather
than infect his family would be guilty of moral weakness if they
changed their mind when faced with putting it into practice.
Hare needs the concept
of ideals as opposed to moral rules in order to set up the real basis
of his argument, which is that although people can logically set
themselves rules by which they can feel that they are acting morally,
whilst undertaking actions which most people would consider immoral,
they can only achieve this at the cost of committing themselves to a
set of ideals, and these ideals involve them in committing themselves
to accept rules which if applied to them as victims most people would
reject. By this route Hare wants to demonstrate that it is only
Liberal ideals which people can not only accept as logical rules by
which to live by, but also which do not involve those who accept them
committing themselves to persecution and suffering in order to
maintain these ideas logically. In short the Liberal does not need
to be a fanatic. This does not mean that the Liberal ideal is any
less of an ideal, but an ideal of a different type.
The Liberal Ideal
Liberal Capitalism in the 19th Century was "fanatical" in its pursuit of profits both at home and throughout its Empire. |
But Hare’s conception
of the Liberal Ideal is both logically and historically flawed. It
is historically flawed for the simple reason that, during the period
that most people would consider the “Golden Age” of Liberalism
i.e. the 19th century, particularly as far as Britain was
concerned, this was specifically the time when these Liberal ideals
and all the paraphernalia that goes with them were being foisted on
the world militarily. Yet this is in direct contradiction to what
Hare says is a fundamental difference between Liberalism and
fanatical ideals i.e. that it does not try to impose itself on to
others by force. Of course the way in which this Liberal ideal was
imposed on other countries also did not live up to the standards of
Liberal behaviour that Hare sets for it. It did not include the
basic idea of political freedom for instance for all those
unfortunate enough to be one of Victoria’s colonial subjects. At
the end of his book Hare has no problem in justifying this basic
contradiction of the concept of Liberty by explaining that, of
course, some people do not understand the idea of political liberty
so they can hardly be seen to be deprived of it, no doubt the Nazi
could use pretty similar arguments for persecuting the Jew. The main
difference between the British Empire’s imposition of the Liberal
Ideal and the Nazis imposition of their ideal was that Britain’s
was imposed, particularly with its economic interest in mind, with
more zeal and barbarity, and with more notable success given the size
of the Empire compared to the Nazis conquests.
Logically, Hare’s
concept is flawed too, because what he fails to draw out is the
extent to which the ideal simply reinforces the status quo. In a
stable society Liberalism can afford to grant permission to others to
hold different ideals so long as those ideals represent no threat, so
long as the existing power relations in society continue. It can do
so precisely because its ideal is dominant. But ideas and ideals are
not something that exist separate from reality and outside men’s
heads. Hare may want to make the assumption that God or Pure Reason
has set out some coda of absolute rules which all we have to do is
discover, but there is no empirical proof to substantiate such an
assumption, and therefore it must be rejected. It was precisely a
change in reality which brought about a change of ideas and ideals
which led many of those who previously held “Liberal” ideals to
support the Nazis when their economic power and privilege was
challenged, and they had rational reasons for doing so. The reason
this change of ideal was rational is precisely because they had
contradictory interests to those who would challenge their wealth and
power. Whilst their ideas and ideals were universalisable, in Hare’s
context, within their own class, they are not universalisable to
society. In short, Hare forgets that society is not some amorphous
mass of individuals whose interests can be reconciled through
negotiation, and who can, therefore, establish some set of common
rules, but is composed of classes each with their own set of rational
ideas, and morals.
Hare comments that the
Liberal novelist is at an advantage over the novelist in the pay of
the fanatic because individuals from their own experience can relate
to sentiments, and these in the novel of the Liberal will be closer
to their own. It would be interesting then to know Hare’s attitude
to the various stories concerning Robin Hood, who is held to be a
national hero, if only a mythical one, and with whom most people can
relate. Yet, what did Robin’s activities amount to in these
stories – stealing, lying, kidnapping etc. etc. In particular
attacks on the life and property of the rich in order to provide for
the poor. Yet these are precisely the ideals, which the modern
Liberal would denounce as the ideals of the fanatic. Hare has the
problem of most Liberals, he does not want to face the fact that real
people have material conflicts of interest. Consequently, he wants
to impose his own middle class interests as being the interests
shared by everyone. If I am on a desert island where there is only
sufficient resources to feed my family, then put myself in the
position of anyone else as I might try to do, empathise with them no
end as I might, I will still in the end look after the interests of
my family, and justify it rationally in the process.
Fanaticism
Hare proposes another
scheme. He suggests we assume that we are omnipotent and propose to
the fanatic that we place him on a planet with others sharing his
ideals, on condition that each share in rotation being those who
suffer as a result of the ideal. The first thing to say is what does
this have to do with the real world? The second thing to say is that
which I have repeated several times, which is that Hare’s own
formulation only requires that people universalise by considering
others in the same relevant position as themselves. Why should the
Nazi consider the position of the Jew in formulating his ideas. This
is like asking the lion to put himself in the position of the
gazelle.
Hare comes close to
recognising the truth once he tries to apply his ideas to the
practical issue of racism in South Africa. He says that any
treatment of the issue of conflict between races (he means ethnic
groups) that doesn’t include history, psychology and politics is
bound to be truncated and superficial. But it is precisely because
it is these sciences which investigate the conditions under which
people live and react that they tell us the more important facts
about how people’s behaviour is determined than the moral
philosophy of how they “ought” to act. In the end a rational
philosophy will grasp that how they “ought” to behave is in fact
determined by the material facts and conditions, including man’s
own effects on his environment and condition, which in turn determine
their ideas and ideals and within which they derive a set of moral
principles rational for them, but not necessarily rational for others
in different conditions.
When Hare says “It is
no use hoping by philosophy alone to convince such people (those with
fanatical views) or to make them change their behaviour”, and then
goes on to say that “Here a deep understanding of psychology is
required before any progress can be hoped for”, he ironically
mimics the attitude of the totalitarian who says, “My view is
rational, you disagree with me so you must be irrational, therefore
you require psychological treatment.” The fact is that the real
counter to the views of the Nazi and the racist is not psychological
treatment or moral argument. The counter is to show that the facts
on which the prejudices are based are fraudulent and to change the
social conditions under which people are prone to accept such
fraudulent facts in the process of looking for scapegoats i.e.
poverty, insecurity, fear etc. It is all these latter which can
group people together as being “in the same condition” and allow
them to “universalise” their prejudices into what appears to be
for them rational moral action.
In furthering his
argument it is precisely to challenging the facts that Hare is forced
to resort. But simply challenging facts is inadequate because this
implies that there is some “absolute truth”. In reality the same
“fact” may be different for different people. Take the rocket
scientist who needs to account for the “fact” that the earth is
round. He will be absolutely correct in asserting the roundness of
the earth as a “fact” to the man levelling the snooker table.
But for this man the relevant “fact” is that the earth is flat,
and it is on the basis of the “fact” of this flatness that he
bases his calculations and actions in levelling the table. For the
capitalist profits are the result of him employing his capital. For
the worker profits are the result of capital exploiting his labour.
For the racist the discrimination against blacks is justified on the
basis of the “fact” that blacks perform badly in IQ tests and
educationally, “proving” their inferiority. For the anti-racist
blacks perform badly in these areas because of the
“fact” they suffer discrimination, deprivation etc. (not to
mention the flawed nature of IQ tests)
Freedom and Reason
Finally, I want to turn
to the actual title of Hare’s book and examine what is Freedom, and
what is Reason. Freedom appears to come down to the ability to
control action. God would be completely free because by definition
God would be capable of doing anything he wished without regard for
even any rules of what is possible because he would make the rules.
In other words God would have complete, unrestricted control over his
actions. As we are not God, clearly our freedom is not absolute, but
operates within some limits. A rock has very little freedom. It has
no control over where, when and how it is formed or anything that
happens to it subsequently. But provided we assume the non-existence
of God or other supernatural forces, there are rules and limits
governing what can happen to it, which in a certain context could be
seen as a kind of freedom. In other words the things that can happen
to it are governed by natural laws rather than its fate being
completely arbitrary or pre-determined.
Every game of snooker
is different because although the same physical laws apply in each
game the application of these laws is different. Although the
trajectory of each ball is governed by the laws of physics and
geometry the moment it is struck a chain reaction of events occurs,
which means that the snooker players original intention (however
skilled) of where the balls should end up can and frequently is
frustrated. Humans are different from either rocks or snooker balls.
Although they are subject to the same kind of natural laws they
possess the ability to analyse the world in which they exist, to
uncover the laws which govern all material things, and human
behaviour, and to use that knowledge to exert some control over their
environment, and to influence and control their environment and their
actions. But, the fact that on this spectrum of freedom and control
Man stands closer to God than the rock, and the greater man’s
knowledge and development the further he moves from the rock, should
not lead us to forget that this freedom and control is not absolute,
but continues to operate within limits and according to rules and
physical and social laws.
Just as man’s freedom
operates within limits rather than being absolute, his reason is
similarly constrained. There can be no Absolute or Pure Reason
applicable for all time and every instance. The worker can apply the
same set of moral reasoning and reach a different conclusion than the
capitalist for instance. Nor might there be agreement on the method
of reasoning. The natural and social laws which govern the
development of the capitalist will determine the reasoning he
applies, and the facts he observes in applying this reason. These
will undoubtedly be different from the facts and reasoning used by
the worker because of their different development, just as a snooker
ball made of ivory will act differently from a snooker ball made of
plastic.
It is unfortunate that
Hare should use the argument alluded to earlier about the inability
of some to recognise the meaning of political liberty, and that he
refers to the inability to govern even if he uses the caveat that
these things can be learned. I doubt were he writing the book today,
rather than in the 1960’s or even when it was reprinted in the late
70’s, he would have used this argument, but in a sense it shows
what is wrong with Hare’s thesis. Attitudes change because
conditions change, people change, and perceptions change. What
appear to be moral principles derived from rational thought today
turn out tomorrow to be prejudice and self-interest.
Labels:
Philosophy
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)