A Critique of R.M. Hare’s “Freedom and Reason”
Descriptive Meaning
Hare wants to argue
that words and judgements share “descriptive meaning”. By this
he wants to make the following logical argument. If I call something
“red” then I am forced to describe everything else with the same
essential properties, which cause me to describe this object as
“red”, “like in the relevant respects” to use Hare’s
phrase, as also being “red”. Similarly, if I describe something
as “good” the “relevant respects” which cause me to make this
judgement must, if they occur in some other instance, cause me to
conclude that this other is also “good”. This is the basis of
“universalisability”. Hare makes clear that in defining
“descriptive meaning” he is not talking about things being
“exactly like” each other because they never are, and this would,
in any case, mean that such “descriptive meaning” and, by
implication, moral rules were trivial.
But, Hare seems unaware
that his looser “like in the relevant respects” suffers
essentially the same problem. It is not just that different people
will see red differently, which Hare recognises, but that the change
from being red to orange is not a discrete but a continuous one. At
some point red stops being red and starts being orange, and yet
identifying this point is in fact impossible, because at this point
red is both red and orange, just as at the point of tangency a circle
is both flat, and not flat. Hare is unable to come to terms with
this because his logic is based on the syllogistic logic of Aristotle
which denies such contradictions. At these inflexion points
syllogistic logic breaks down, and dialectics takes over.
For the same individual
if the length of light waves is gradually changed then red becomes
orange. Through a whole range the “relevant respects” allow him
to continue to describe every hue he sees as “red”, but at some
point he will describe the colour not as “red” but “orange”.
It will always be possible to make smaller and smaller adjustments to
the wavelength such that our individual will change his description
between “red” and “orange”, and may even over very small time
periods describe the same frequency at one time as “red” and at
another as “orange”. Nor is this problem resolved by describing
“orange” as a type of “red”, as Hare does with “Scarlet”
etc., because applying the same process we would end up through
“yellow” and “green” to “blue”, thereby arriving at the
ridiculous conclusion of describing “blue” as a variant of “red”.
Blue can, of course be described as a variant of red only in the
sense that red is a variant of blue i.e. they are both colours.
Non-Triviality
But it is precisely at
the inflexion points that the importance and non-triviality exist.
If we transfer the issue over to the real purpose of Hare’s concern
– morals – then a thesis which only allows the development of
rules for situations which are as clear-cut as the difference between
“red” and “blue” is trivial indeed. The non-triviality is to
provide a basis for those situations which are not clear-cut. To
transfer the argument used above to a moral dilemma let us try to put
this into the kind of formulation that Hare proposes.
“It is good to kill
someone if this is done as an act of self-defence of another innocent
human being.”
There may be many
clear-cut instances where this judgement is true. A policeman shoots
a known serial killer and child molester holding a knife at a young
child’s throat, for instance. Though even here the policeman
cannot be sure the individual would actually kill the child. But
there may be many gradations of this which possess the “like in the
relevant respects”, but which may cause a different course of
action. For example, I hear X in the pub say “I am going to kill
Y.” Few people would say this justified me in killing X in order
to save Y’s life. For one thing I would want to know whether X was
speaking literally, what was the seriousness of his intent?
Moreover, such a situation lacks immediacy. Other courses of action
are open such as warning Y, informing the police etc.
The Truth Is Always Concrete
Lenin summed up the basis of dialectics in the phrase "The truth is always concrete." |
But, suppose I know
that X has some reason to threaten Y, and Y is about to come into the
pub? Still there may be other options rather than me killing X.
Suppose Y comes into the pub, and I see X pull a gun out of a bag
under the table? But, still I don’t know if this is a real gun, if
it is loaded, if X really does intend to kill Y or just scare him.
Suppose, X attracts Y’s attention by firing into the ceiling
causing plaster to fall and shouting out to him in abusive terms. I
now know that the gun is real and had at least one bullet. Yet Y may
escape, X might not be a good shot, he could miss etc. etc. Would I
be entitled to shoot him if I had my own gun? Suppose I knew that X
was a crack shot in the army and unlikely to miss, and had killed
before, would I be acting morally if I shot him then?
Only by using rules
which are completely prescriptive could these questions be resolved,
but with such a level of prescription rather than a universal rule we
have a particular rule rather than a universal one. In the end,
Hare’s formulation comes down to what he wanted to avoid by trying
to escape describing situations as exactly the same. “Like in the
relevant respects” merely allows us to provide universal rules for
clear-cut instances i.e. it becomes trivial, whereas the more tricky
instances where philosophical analysis should be most important
demonstrates the impotence of Hare’s approach.
Hare argues that what
is important about words like “good” is their prescriptive
meaning. He contrasts this with other moral words like
“industrious”. For “industrious” its descriptive meaning is
primary and its prescriptive meaning secondary. A society may see
“industriousness” not as a moral positive, but as a negative.
Its descriptive meaning would remain the same, but its prescriptive
meaning i.e. as a recommended action would have changed. However,
Hare says, if we considered a man “good” because he was
industrious the change in the prescriptive meaning of industrious
does not mean we no longer consider the man “good”. There may be
other reasons for calling him “good”. If the descriptive meaning
of “good” changes to no longer include industrious as one of its
attributes, one of the “relevant respects” which cause us to
describe someone as “good”, this does not change the prescriptive
meaning of “good”. In other words Hare wants to set aside words
like “good” from other words like “industrious” which may
form attributes of what constitutes “good”. "Good" will then
always have a prescriptive meaning which is positive, however much
its descriptive meaning changes.
But this is the problem
with language. For example, it became part of the language of youth
to refer to people/things positively as “bad”, as in “that
brother is bad”, or “that is one bad piece of music”. Here the
meaning of “bad” is positive not negative, and to give the
converse of this it is often that people use the term “do-gooder”
not in a prescriptively positive but negative sense.
Hare also uses the
example of the word “nigger” to show that this could not be used
if one wanted to speak to a black person as an equal. Yet it is
perhaps an indication of the increased confidence of black people
that they now refer to each other in those terms without any sense of
shame.
Hare argues that
differences of opinion over descriptive meaning can be resolved by
agreeing a definition whereas such differences in relation to value
terms cannot. He uses the example of cutting down trees, and the
question of what constitutes a tree rather than a bush. This would
appear straightforward. But as the line he draws demonstrates it is
not so straightforward. He suggests it does not matter if we call
the thing in question a tree or a bush provided we agree to cut down
everything under 15 feet with the lowest branch at least 3 feet from
the ground. Yet this would include young trees, which are not
bushes. In fact a far more detailed description is required to
distinguish trees from bushes, and there is no reason why two
individuals should agree to every aspect of these details. If the
requirement is to cut down every bush then unless an agreement on
what constitutes a bush can be reached then an agreed course of
action cannot follow. To simply say cut down everything below 15
feet etc. is to change the terms of the problem, not to resolve the
problem.
Universality
Hare sets out a
definition of “Universality” which is different from Kant's Categorical Imperative, although later on the difference is somewhat
fudged in his application of “Universality”. The CI says I can
only judge a decision to be moral if I could will such an act to be
adopted by everyone. Hare’s “Universality”, however, only
requires that the act be capable of being adopted by people in the
same situation, or “relevantly similar circumstances” as Hare
puts it. It is in the definition of what constitutes “relevantly
similar circumstances” that the blurring occurs later on. So, for
example, suppose I am poor. I ask myself “Is it moral to steal
from the rich?" (I might use Hare’s method of defining rich used in
the example of the bush and the trees i.e. wealth above a certain
amount). I think yes. Then I ask is this universalisable to others
in the same position? Again I think yes, because, being poor, I am
in no danger of willing an act of theft against myself to be moral.
Under, Hare’s approach then it is quite logical for the poor to
consider stealing from the rich to be moral. This is not the case
with the CI because it is not limited to people in the same position.
I would have to ask is it possible for everyone to adopt this rule
and it would be clear that the rich would have no reason to adopt it.
Hare faced with the contradiction which his formulation creates in
practice, changes the formulation so that instead of the individual
asking could he accept such a rule being adopted by others in the
same situation he changes the test so that the individual is asked to
step outside reality, and to put himself in the position of someone
who might suffer from the application of the rule, in other words
someone not in the same position. But this effectively removes the
difference with the CI.
Petit-Bourgeois Morality
Hare gives the example
of someone being forced to shore in a boat to distinguish the
question “Shall I be forced on to shore?” as being really “Will
I be forced on to shore” rather than a request for guidance. From
this he gives an example of an honest and dishonest cashier. The
dishonest cashier suggests to the other he take money for his
holidays. Hare argues that although neuroscience might show that
such a person would never commit such an act they would still ask the
question, and their action is still a moral act resulting from asking
the question. But does this hold in reverse. If neuroscience shows
the dishonest cashier will inevitably take the money can we say they
would even ask the question. If I am hungry and have appetising food
placed in front of me, I do not ask myself the question “Shall I
eat”, I just eat. If the dishonest cashier is physically
conditioned, either by nature or by nurture to take what they need
then if they need money and see the opportunity to take some, why
would they ask whether or not they should? Hare also says that
scientific advancement showing that people are conditioned to act in
a particular way does not mean we can then abstain from making moral
judgements of people’s actions. But either this is sterile or
contradicts Hare’s thesis. If “universal” only means other
people in the same condition and circumstances then how can I judge
whether someone else acted morally. I can ask myself whether I would
have acted as they did knowing my condition and circumstance, but
this tells me nothing about the morality of their
action because their position and circumstance is not mine.
The rules of all games favour the strengths of some players as against the weaknesses of others. The important question is, "Who creates the rules?" |
Hare argues that ethics
is morally neutral. He makes a parallel with the rules of games,
arguing that the rules of a game are neutral between the players.
But this is clearly false. If I know the strengths and weaknesses of
the players, then it is a simple matter to construct rules, which
favour the strengths of one player and diminish the chances of the
other. A moral equivalent might be to say that no one should steal.
Is such a rule neutral? No. If you are rich you have not the same
need to steal as someone poor. The important question here then is
who makes the rules. It is invariably the most powerful, wealthy and
privileged, and it is not surprising then that the rules they make,
whilst masquerading as neutral, in fact are designed to ensure their
supremacy, power, wealth and privilege is maintained.
Hare’s version of
“universalisable” as compared with Kant’s, however, does
provide the freedom for those not part of this dominant group to
define their own morality in contrast to it. Because Hare’s
“universalisable” is limited to those in similar circumstances
not to everyone. So the working class could, for instance, decide
its members were all in the same circumstance and find it morally
positive to deprive the capitalists of their property. As such a
decision for each member of the working class only has to pass the
test “could this decision be universalisable to others in the same
position i.e. other workers” then this meets Hare’s criterion.
As this results in conclusions which infringe Hare’s Liberal
ideology he is forced in practice to abandon this formulation later
on without recognising he has done so.
Morality - Uncomfortable Conclusions
Hare then gives an
example of how his formulation could be applied. He gives the
example of someone (B) owed money by (A) who asks himself whether A
should be put in gaol. The example seems to fail for a number of
reasons, some of which Hare admits. Hare suggests that in deciding
the person should consider his position if he owed a third person (C)
money, and whether his rule would then justify this third person
having him gaoled. Hare argues that as in general people do not want
to be put in gaol he would not wish C to do this to him, and
therefore could not adopt it as a principle in relation to A. But as
Hare recognises B could feel that C should indeed put him in prison
even though he would lose out from this. Secondly, the “in similar
circumstances” here does not explore what else might need to be
known about A, B and C. For instance, A might be rich and capable of
paying B but refuses. B might be poor and only owes C because A has
not paid him. The sensible course then might be for B and C to
combine and threaten A with gaol unless he paid up because
essentially A owes both B and C.
This is the problem
with the concept of “universalisable”. Nearly every situation is
different. In this latter case the shared interest of both B and C
puts them both in a class as against A, but leads B to conclude
morally that A should go to gaol, but also to conclude that C should
not send him to gaol, because the situation is different. Hare’s
reasoning seems to result in strange conclusions, which he finds
himself having to go into contortions later on to resolve. If we
change the above example this can be demonstrated. B considers
whether A should be punished for committing murder. He concludes
that as he would not want to be punished if he committed murder then
A should face no sanction!! Hare retorts in the case of B arguing
for imprisonment on the basis of his principled belief in the
sanctity of property and contracts that such a position could be
defended if he can show that laxity of enforcement would have serious
consequences for society. But again this is to assume that all
members of society have the same interests and this is a false
assumption. In a society made up of debtors and creditors the
creditors would no doubt agree with B’s principled stand, but it is
unlikely the debtors would share it. The issue then resolves not
into questions of freedom or reason, but of power and control, of who
sets the rules.
Hare retorts on the
question of there being differences between A and B’s cases that
first of all he has hypothesised the case away. But rules including
moral rules are only useful if they deal with actual reality rather
than hypothesised fantasy. If in reality the hypothetical
equivalence of A, B and C cannot exist (and it cannot) then rules
based on that equality are at best useless, and at worst misleading.
The appeal to “universalisability” that Hare uses as his second
response does not work either. If I am poor and always expect to be
poor there is little point in asking me to put myself in the place of
the rich. If I am a white, Aryan Nazi, there is little point in
asking me to put myself in the place of the Jew. Whilst I might, and
do, abhor the moral decisions the Nazi arrives at I cannot deny using
Hare’s own method of developing moral rules the Nazi’s are as
justified as anyone else’s. He examines the “facts” as he sees
them, and asks “Could others in the same position as me (i.e.
white, Aryan, Nazis) arrive at the same decisions", and concludes
“Yes”.
In the end, Hare's Moral rules come down to the same presentation of the ideas and interests of the petit-bourgeois, as universal, as that of Bentham. |
But it is here that
Hare moves away from his original formulation when confronted with
this result, effectively adopting the Kantian position. He no longer
sees “universalisability” as the ability to view things from the
actual position of the given real individual, and all others in the
same position, but from the standpoint of some non-existent, abstract
individual. Once again we are led into making moral rules not based
on reality, but fantastic hypotheticals. The consequence is that
instead of Hare’s philosophy providing a basis for understanding
human behaviour and morals it does the opposite. He is left
describing people like the Nazis as fanatics because although the
true Nazi is untouched by Hare’s theory, in order to justify the
rationality of his moral rules i.e. he has to say “if I were a Jew
I would want to be killed and persecuted”, this belief in itself
must be seen as so irrational that only a few could hold it
consistently. But it is only by understanding that given the
circumstances Nazis can view their morality, ideas and actions as
rational that we can understand the development of those ideas. On
Hare’s philosophy the development of such forces and ideas is
inexplicable other than by labelling them as fanatical. The converse
of this of course is that there is some set of rational ideas and
morals that is “universalisable” to everyone, and effectively
Hare sees these as being those that come under the heading of
“Liberalism”.
Fanaticism and Rationality
Hare goes on to phrase
the question as “What do you say in a hypothetical case in which
you are in your victim’s position?” If we put this back to the
example I gave earlier where A is a murderer, B faces the question
“should I punish A?” If B puts himself in the hypothetical
situation of being a murderer would he want to be punished? The
question is in many ways ludicrous because B can never know what he
would feel unless he were actually in that position. But, were B to
say “Yes, I should be punished”, would we want to call him a
fanatic. But for the Nazi with a deep seated hatred of Jews based on
what they believe to be facts, the idea that as a race they were
responsible for the death of Christ, that they are sub-human and all
the other nonsense, it is quite logical for such a Nazi to say “If
I were one of these people I would expect to be punished”, just as
it is logical for most humans to say they would expect to be punished
if they were a murderer.
Who were the real fanatics? The Spanish Inquisition or the heretics they persecuted? |
Hare’s problem is
that he wants to use his own perceptions and prejudices to define
what is rational for everyone else. For although, he says there is
no logical reason for someone not to hold these views he labels those
that do “fanatics” and bases this on the idea that those that
hold them are a minority. But by this token if they were a majority
then the minority that didn’t hold them would be fanatics. This
seems to be moral decision making by populism. A similar approach is
taken when Hare retorts to the issue of criminal behaviour. He says
that a judge when faced with the question “would I like to be put
into prison were I the criminal” has to take into consideration the
interests of society. Besides the fact that this is removed from
Hare’s original methodology of how to decide on moral issues it
does not seem to provide the solution he requires. As a member of
society and moral individual doesn’t the creditor take this into
account too, indeed doesn’t the Nazi take into account what he sees
as the interest of society. Moreover, the quantity of people
involved doesn’t logically seem to change the end decision. If all
individuals were asked the question “would you like to be put in
prison?” according to Hare’s version of what a rational response
would be unless they were fanatics the answer would be “No.” And
if as Hare argues the judge is there to represent the community his
response should also be that the criminal should not be imprisoned
otherwise his view is contrary to the view of society.
Hare’s argument that
the judge can say to the criminal “I find it easier to adopt the
maxim ‘thieves should be put in prison’” is a cop-out because
it is answering a different moral question than the one he has posed.
All he has demonstrated is that different moral rules conflict with
each other. Suppose I adopt a moral rule “People ought not commit
murder”. This does not tell me what the consequence should be if
someone does commit murder. If I have another moral rule that says
“Murderer’s should not be punished” based on my own aversion to
punishment then I am left merely with the fact that in committing
murder they act immorally but cannot punish them without acting
immorally myself. If I then act immorally and punish them, who
punishes me, and so on.
Moreover, the argument
Hare uses to arrive at this new maxim is very dangerous. He says the
judge might reason that unless the criminal is punished he might rob
others, or other people might follow his example and rob. If we then
use these two arguments the judge might be asked “Would you like to
be punished for things you have not yet done?” Or, “Would you
like to be punished for things done by other people?” This kind of
argument would lead to all kinds of arbitrary punishment.
Hare gives another
example using a chocolate bar. He says if three equal people come to
share a chocolate bar they can morally agree to have a third each.
If one does not like chocolate they can reach a universal decision
that those that don’t like chocolate should not be given any, and
consequently it be divided into two. But the third party could
equally logically come to the conclusion that no one should have any.
They have nothing to gain by the first decision, and might even feel
deprived as a result of it. They may feel better with the second
decision though the other two will likely disagree. The decision of
both groups is universal only to its own group.
Utility
Hare goes on in some
detail in respect of utilitarian methods of arriving at moral
decisions. He says he has some sympathy with the “rule-utilitarian”
system modified by particular instances to arrive at less general
rules. I have little to say here other than that “utility” as a
concept in morals suffers the same problems it does in economics i.e.
it is unmeasurable. It is, therefore, impossible to maximise because
to do so requires the ability to compare one quantity of utility with
another. Like its economic counterpart utility in this context is
fine for those sitting in ivory towers developing theories based on
fantastic hypotheticals but has no grounding in reality.
Hare then moves on to a
discussion of aesthetics, which takes us back to the beginning of the
discussion and the issue of “like in the relevant respects”.
Hare uses the example of Siamese cats to say that if we describe one
as “beautiful” then we are compelled to say that all others
“alike in the relevant respects” are also beautiful. But there
is a logical problem here similar to that encountered at the
beginning. If I take two cats, not identical but “alike in the
relevant respects” then if I call the first beautiful then I will
call the second beautiful too. But suppose I introduce a third cat,
which is like the second in all the relevant respects but less like
the first than the second. As I introduce further cats they may be
almost identical to the one before it but less and less like the
first. The more cats we introduce the less reason we have to call
these cats beautiful just because that was how we categorised the
first. Quantity has been transformed into quality. The only way to
avoid this is to give the words “alike in the relevant respects”
the meaning “identical”, but that is what Hare wants to avoid
because he knows that such identity does not exist.
Morality - Idealism v Materialism
Hare wants to argue
that conflicts of interest are resolvable through negotiation and
bargaining whereas conflicts of ideals are not. But this is somewhat
facile. If there is a fundamental conflict of interest e.g. between
workers and capitalists a modus vivendi may be reached based on
bargaining as happens with Trade Unions, but this does not resolve
the conflict which continues to exist and to manifest itself over and
over until such time as the basis of the conflict is removed. The
same is true of Hare’s example of World War II which he wrongly
ascribes as being a conflict of ideals between Nazism and Liberalism.
Such a description is clearly false when one considers that not only
did liberal democracy fail to counter fascism in Italy during the
1920’s or in Germany in the 1930’s, but leading representatives
of Liberal democracy openly welcomed it. And during the Spanish
Civil War democracy failed to come to the support of those fighting
fascism even with such modest means as the supply of arms. The real
basis of the war was not a conflict of ideals, but was precisely a
conflict of economic interest. Both groups had no difficulty in
universalising their own respective economic interest into a moral
justification of their actions. Moreover, far from the
intractability of the Nazis ideals being a barrier to resolution with
the Liberal ideals in Britain and the US, it did not prevent the US
from staying out of the war until it was half way through, nor of
many in the US believing then and afterwards that they should have
been fighting on the other side, nor indeed of America and Britain
supporting regimes with similar ideals both then and since.
Contrary to Hare’s
assertion, experience particularly since WWII has been that
conflicting ideals are negotiable in terms of which states to support
and deal with provided that it is to the end of promoting economic or
other strategic interest. This was demonstrably true of the US
during WWII, which, despite the fact of knowing exactly what ideals
the Nazis had and how they were treating Jews, continued to trade
with them, US companies continued to operate in Germany including
those being used to manufacture weapons used against Jews and British
soldiers. The US did not have the same economic conflict with
Germany that Britain did. The US had an economic conflict with
Japan, with whom it went to war, thus bringing it into war against
Germany as Japan’s ally.
But it is in the
question of ideals that Hare needed to make the change in the way he
defines “universalisable”. Originally, his definition was “could
other people like me in the relevant respects make the same decision
on questions like this one.” On this basis the Nazis logic does
not require resort to “ideals” but merely to imagine that other
Nazis can come to the same conclusion. To ask him to put himself in
the place of the Jew as Hare now requires him to do is to ask him to
put himself in the place of someone different to him “in the
relevant respects” and thereby to contradict the original
formulation.
Hare then uses a
different argument based upon his discussion of aesthetics. He
argues that just because I hate a piece of music does not mean I have
a moral duty to disrupt its performance. Similarly, the Nazis hatred
of Jews does not mean they have a moral duty to persecute them. But
this is a straw man. Changing the terms of this argument defeats it.
If instead of a piece of music I place the smallpox bacteria then my
hatred of it, and concern for its effects on others would logically
lead me to believe I should act on this and try to eradicate it.
However perverse and disgusting, the Nazis viewed the Jews almost
exactly in this light so Hare’s argument does not seem to apply.
He proposes a trick to
expose the Nazis illogicality or fanaticism. He proposes making the
Nazi believe that he is a Jew, and seeing if his opinion then
changes. If it does then his moral rule is illogical, if it does not
then he is a fanatic. A bit like the old test for witches by
drowning them. If they didn’t drown they were a witch, if they did
they were not. But this trick fails Hare’s original formulation of
“like in the relevant respects”. If we go back to Hare’s
original discussion about red, and what is necessary for something to
be called red, we could put red in the place of Nazi and see that the
condition is not met. If a condition of redness is not being blue,
and a condition of being a Nazi is not being a Jew (at least in the
sense of being a 1930’s German Nazi) then it is clear that a
significant failure of Hare’s argument arises here. Hare proceeded
to say that everything else containing the essential elements of
“red” lead us to say that everything else containing these must
be red, and that we are committed to saying so. In order for
universalisability to happen it is necessary that everyone who is
like me “in the relevant respects” should be able to come to the
same conclusion that this is red. Presumably a blind person could
not because they are not like me.
But as soon as I trick
the Nazi into believing he is a Jew “the relevant respects” of
what made him a Nazi have changed. He is now free to assess his new
position and to adopt a new set of rules appropriate to it. If we
ask the Nazi then to apply Hare’s rule he says “I am a Nazi, I
should exterminate Jews, can I universalise this rule by saying
anyone else in similar circumstances i.e. being a Nazi should act the
same?” He says “Yes.” Once he no longer believes himself to
be a Nazi because of being a Jew this link to others being “in
relevantly similar circumstances” is broken.
The argument Hare then
uses about people being very rare who would want to be killed
themselves e.g. if they were themselves a Jew is weak. Suppose I ask
myself “Were I to contract an awful infectious disease and might
infect my family causing a horrible death, and the only way to avoid
this would be to be killed and have my body burned, should I do
this?” The fact that the prospect is remote might help me to
assent to such a principle, but there are many who would do so, and
be considered very moral for it. As the Nazi feels the same way
about the Jew it is not unrealistic to believe that such a principle
would be rational. It does not matter that the basis on which the
Nazi bases his evaluation is a gross perversion of truth, because
people can only be requested to base their decisions on the basis of
the facts as they perceive them. Given that there are not a few
supposedly reputable psychologists in the liberal democracies who
over the years have presented papers supposedly showing that black
people, or working class people have lower IQ’s, it is not
surprising that people can be convinced of such ideas.
If we then go back to
Hare’s trick then if the Nazi changed his mind when made to believe
that he was a Jew this could be interpreted as moral weakness, just
as the man who agrees to the principle he should be sacrificed rather
than infect his family would be guilty of moral weakness if they
changed their mind when faced with putting it into practice.
Hare needs the concept
of ideals as opposed to moral rules in order to set up the real basis
of his argument, which is that although people can logically set
themselves rules by which they can feel that they are acting morally,
whilst undertaking actions which most people would consider immoral,
they can only achieve this at the cost of committing themselves to a
set of ideals, and these ideals involve them in committing themselves
to accept rules which if applied to them as victims most people would
reject. By this route Hare wants to demonstrate that it is only
Liberal ideals which people can not only accept as logical rules by
which to live by, but also which do not involve those who accept them
committing themselves to persecution and suffering in order to
maintain these ideas logically. In short the Liberal does not need
to be a fanatic. This does not mean that the Liberal ideal is any
less of an ideal, but an ideal of a different type.
The Liberal Ideal
Liberal Capitalism in the 19th Century was "fanatical" in its pursuit of profits both at home and throughout its Empire. |
But Hare’s conception
of the Liberal Ideal is both logically and historically flawed. It
is historically flawed for the simple reason that, during the period
that most people would consider the “Golden Age” of Liberalism
i.e. the 19th century, particularly as far as Britain was
concerned, this was specifically the time when these Liberal ideals
and all the paraphernalia that goes with them were being foisted on
the world militarily. Yet this is in direct contradiction to what
Hare says is a fundamental difference between Liberalism and
fanatical ideals i.e. that it does not try to impose itself on to
others by force. Of course the way in which this Liberal ideal was
imposed on other countries also did not live up to the standards of
Liberal behaviour that Hare sets for it. It did not include the
basic idea of political freedom for instance for all those
unfortunate enough to be one of Victoria’s colonial subjects. At
the end of his book Hare has no problem in justifying this basic
contradiction of the concept of Liberty by explaining that, of
course, some people do not understand the idea of political liberty
so they can hardly be seen to be deprived of it, no doubt the Nazi
could use pretty similar arguments for persecuting the Jew. The main
difference between the British Empire’s imposition of the Liberal
Ideal and the Nazis imposition of their ideal was that Britain’s
was imposed, particularly with its economic interest in mind, with
more zeal and barbarity, and with more notable success given the size
of the Empire compared to the Nazis conquests.
Logically, Hare’s
concept is flawed too, because what he fails to draw out is the
extent to which the ideal simply reinforces the status quo. In a
stable society Liberalism can afford to grant permission to others to
hold different ideals so long as those ideals represent no threat, so
long as the existing power relations in society continue. It can do
so precisely because its ideal is dominant. But ideas and ideals are
not something that exist separate from reality and outside men’s
heads. Hare may want to make the assumption that God or Pure Reason
has set out some coda of absolute rules which all we have to do is
discover, but there is no empirical proof to substantiate such an
assumption, and therefore it must be rejected. It was precisely a
change in reality which brought about a change of ideas and ideals
which led many of those who previously held “Liberal” ideals to
support the Nazis when their economic power and privilege was
challenged, and they had rational reasons for doing so. The reason
this change of ideal was rational is precisely because they had
contradictory interests to those who would challenge their wealth and
power. Whilst their ideas and ideals were universalisable, in Hare’s
context, within their own class, they are not universalisable to
society. In short, Hare forgets that society is not some amorphous
mass of individuals whose interests can be reconciled through
negotiation, and who can, therefore, establish some set of common
rules, but is composed of classes each with their own set of rational
ideas, and morals.
Hare comments that the
Liberal novelist is at an advantage over the novelist in the pay of
the fanatic because individuals from their own experience can relate
to sentiments, and these in the novel of the Liberal will be closer
to their own. It would be interesting then to know Hare’s attitude
to the various stories concerning Robin Hood, who is held to be a
national hero, if only a mythical one, and with whom most people can
relate. Yet, what did Robin’s activities amount to in these
stories – stealing, lying, kidnapping etc. etc. In particular
attacks on the life and property of the rich in order to provide for
the poor. Yet these are precisely the ideals, which the modern
Liberal would denounce as the ideals of the fanatic. Hare has the
problem of most Liberals, he does not want to face the fact that real
people have material conflicts of interest. Consequently, he wants
to impose his own middle class interests as being the interests
shared by everyone. If I am on a desert island where there is only
sufficient resources to feed my family, then put myself in the
position of anyone else as I might try to do, empathise with them no
end as I might, I will still in the end look after the interests of
my family, and justify it rationally in the process.
Fanaticism
Hare proposes another
scheme. He suggests we assume that we are omnipotent and propose to
the fanatic that we place him on a planet with others sharing his
ideals, on condition that each share in rotation being those who
suffer as a result of the ideal. The first thing to say is what does
this have to do with the real world? The second thing to say is that
which I have repeated several times, which is that Hare’s own
formulation only requires that people universalise by considering
others in the same relevant position as themselves. Why should the
Nazi consider the position of the Jew in formulating his ideas. This
is like asking the lion to put himself in the position of the
gazelle.
Hare comes close to
recognising the truth once he tries to apply his ideas to the
practical issue of racism in South Africa. He says that any
treatment of the issue of conflict between races (he means ethnic
groups) that doesn’t include history, psychology and politics is
bound to be truncated and superficial. But it is precisely because
it is these sciences which investigate the conditions under which
people live and react that they tell us the more important facts
about how people’s behaviour is determined than the moral
philosophy of how they “ought” to act. In the end a rational
philosophy will grasp that how they “ought” to behave is in fact
determined by the material facts and conditions, including man’s
own effects on his environment and condition, which in turn determine
their ideas and ideals and within which they derive a set of moral
principles rational for them, but not necessarily rational for others
in different conditions.
When Hare says “It is
no use hoping by philosophy alone to convince such people (those with
fanatical views) or to make them change their behaviour”, and then
goes on to say that “Here a deep understanding of psychology is
required before any progress can be hoped for”, he ironically
mimics the attitude of the totalitarian who says, “My view is
rational, you disagree with me so you must be irrational, therefore
you require psychological treatment.” The fact is that the real
counter to the views of the Nazi and the racist is not psychological
treatment or moral argument. The counter is to show that the facts
on which the prejudices are based are fraudulent and to change the
social conditions under which people are prone to accept such
fraudulent facts in the process of looking for scapegoats i.e.
poverty, insecurity, fear etc. It is all these latter which can
group people together as being “in the same condition” and allow
them to “universalise” their prejudices into what appears to be
for them rational moral action.
In furthering his
argument it is precisely to challenging the facts that Hare is forced
to resort. But simply challenging facts is inadequate because this
implies that there is some “absolute truth”. In reality the same
“fact” may be different for different people. Take the rocket
scientist who needs to account for the “fact” that the earth is
round. He will be absolutely correct in asserting the roundness of
the earth as a “fact” to the man levelling the snooker table.
But for this man the relevant “fact” is that the earth is flat,
and it is on the basis of the “fact” of this flatness that he
bases his calculations and actions in levelling the table. For the
capitalist profits are the result of him employing his capital. For
the worker profits are the result of capital exploiting his labour.
For the racist the discrimination against blacks is justified on the
basis of the “fact” that blacks perform badly in IQ tests and
educationally, “proving” their inferiority. For the anti-racist
blacks perform badly in these areas because of the
“fact” they suffer discrimination, deprivation etc. (not to
mention the flawed nature of IQ tests)
Freedom and Reason
Finally, I want to turn
to the actual title of Hare’s book and examine what is Freedom, and
what is Reason. Freedom appears to come down to the ability to
control action. God would be completely free because by definition
God would be capable of doing anything he wished without regard for
even any rules of what is possible because he would make the rules.
In other words God would have complete, unrestricted control over his
actions. As we are not God, clearly our freedom is not absolute, but
operates within some limits. A rock has very little freedom. It has
no control over where, when and how it is formed or anything that
happens to it subsequently. But provided we assume the non-existence
of God or other supernatural forces, there are rules and limits
governing what can happen to it, which in a certain context could be
seen as a kind of freedom. In other words the things that can happen
to it are governed by natural laws rather than its fate being
completely arbitrary or pre-determined.
Every game of snooker
is different because although the same physical laws apply in each
game the application of these laws is different. Although the
trajectory of each ball is governed by the laws of physics and
geometry the moment it is struck a chain reaction of events occurs,
which means that the snooker players original intention (however
skilled) of where the balls should end up can and frequently is
frustrated. Humans are different from either rocks or snooker balls.
Although they are subject to the same kind of natural laws they
possess the ability to analyse the world in which they exist, to
uncover the laws which govern all material things, and human
behaviour, and to use that knowledge to exert some control over their
environment, and to influence and control their environment and their
actions. But, the fact that on this spectrum of freedom and control
Man stands closer to God than the rock, and the greater man’s
knowledge and development the further he moves from the rock, should
not lead us to forget that this freedom and control is not absolute,
but continues to operate within limits and according to rules and
physical and social laws.
Just as man’s freedom
operates within limits rather than being absolute, his reason is
similarly constrained. There can be no Absolute or Pure Reason
applicable for all time and every instance. The worker can apply the
same set of moral reasoning and reach a different conclusion than the
capitalist for instance. Nor might there be agreement on the method
of reasoning. The natural and social laws which govern the
development of the capitalist will determine the reasoning he
applies, and the facts he observes in applying this reason. These
will undoubtedly be different from the facts and reasoning used by
the worker because of their different development, just as a snooker
ball made of ivory will act differently from a snooker ball made of
plastic.
It is unfortunate that
Hare should use the argument alluded to earlier about the inability
of some to recognise the meaning of political liberty, and that he
refers to the inability to govern even if he uses the caveat that
these things can be learned. I doubt were he writing the book today,
rather than in the 1960’s or even when it was reprinted in the late
70’s, he would have used this argument, but in a sense it shows
what is wrong with Hare’s thesis. Attitudes change because
conditions change, people change, and perceptions change. What
appear to be moral principles derived from rational thought today
turn out tomorrow to be prejudice and self-interest.
No comments:
Post a Comment