Contradictions In The General Formula Of Capital
Some of the
contradictions alluded to in the previous chapter are drawn out here
by Marx, as part of his dialectical exposition. He starts by
pointing out that for two out of the three people involved in the
transactions, things do not look differently to what they were
previously. If a capitalist buys commodities from A and sells them
to B, then from A's perspective things still appear as they were
before for him as a seller i.e. C-M. And for B as a buyer they still
appear as M-C. For both, as commodity producers these stages still
seem to be within the process, C-M-C.
But, herein
lies the contradiction referred to previously. If things really do
appear the same to A and B, it is impossible for C to derive a
profit, because such a profit here can only be derived as a result of
buying the commodity below its Value, or selling it above its Value
or both. Yet, its clear that Merchants did and do make profits.
What Marx is doing here again is taking us through an historical and
logical process to demonstrate how this contradiction is rooted in
reality, and how it is resolved.
“The inversion, therefore, of the order of succession, does not
take us outside the sphere of the simple circulation of commodities,
and we must rather look, whether there is in this simple circulation
anything permitting an expansion of the value that enters into
circulation, and, consequently, a creation of surplus-value.” (p
155)
To answer
this question, Marx goes back a stage to a barter arrangement where
one commodity (Use Value) is exchanged for another. Marx introduces
here also the concept of Absolute Comparative Advantage. Both
parties have gained from the exchange because they have exchanged a
Use Value they did not want for one they did (what orthodox economics
calls a gain in welfare), but also,
“..
there may also be a further gain. A, who sells wine and buys corn,
possibly produces more wine, with given labour-time, than farmer B
could, and B on the other hand, more corn than wine-grower A could.
A, therefore, may get, for the same exchange-value, more corn, and B
more wine, than each would respectively get without any exchange by
producing his own corn and wine.” (p 155)
But, this
increase in welfare or real wealth (i.e. Use Value) does not at all
mean that there is any increase in Exchange Value resulting from this
exchange. On the contrary, as was seen in Chapter 1, it is usually
the case than an increase in real wealth, in the number of Use
Values, goes hand in hand with a fall in Exchange Value, because the
cause of the rise in the quantity of Use Value (a rise in
productivity) is at the same time a cause of a fall in the
labour-time required for the production of those Use Values, and,
therefore, of their Value!
Marx quotes
La Mercier de la Rivière
““A
man who has plenty of wine and no corn treats with a man who has
plenty of corn and no wine; an exchange takes place between them of
corn to the value of 50, for wine of the same value. This act
produces no increase of exchange-value either for the one or the
other; for each of them already possessed, before the exchange, a
value equal to that which he acquired by means of that operation.””
(p 155)
As Marx
states,
“The
result is not altered by introducing money, as a medium of
circulation, between the commodities, and making the sale and the
purchase two distinct acts. The value of a commodity is expressed in
its price before it goes into circulation, and is therefore a
precedent condition of circulation, not its result.” (p 155-6)
“It is
true, commodities may be sold at prices deviating from their values,
but these deviations are to be considered as infractions of the laws
of the exchange of commodities, which in its normal state is an
exchange of equivalents, consequently, no method for increasing
value.” (p 156)
This is the
opposite of the position of orthodox economics, particularly of the
Austrian School, which sees precisely in this gain in welfare the
basis of profit. As Marx points out, this is to confuse Use Value
with Exchange Value. Orthodox economics resorts to this device
because it is unable to account for the existence of profit. It can
provide all sorts of justifications for capitalists receiving profit,
such as abstinence, risk-taking and so on, but none of these explain
where the profit they receive for these virtues actually comes from!
Its like a physician settling for an explanation of Syphilis by
claiming that the “Wages of Sin Is Death”. In fact, according to
orthodox economic theory, profit should NOT exist at all, because
competition should eliminate it!
Marx quotes
an early example of this argument by Condillac.
“For
instance, Condillac says: “It is not true that on an exchange of
commodities we give value for value. On the contrary, each of the two
contracting parties in every case, gives a less for a greater value.
... If we really exchanged equal values, neither party could make a
profit. And yet, they both gain, or ought to gain. Why? The value of
a thing consists solely in its relation to our wants. What is more to
the one is less to the other, and vice versâ.
... It is not to be assumed that we offer for sale articles required
for our own consumption. ... We wish to part with a useless thing, in
order to get one that we need; we want to give less for more. ... It
was natural to think that, in an exchange, value was given for value,
whenever each of the articles exchanged was of equal value with the
same quantity of gold. ... But there is another point to be
considered in our calculation. The question is, whether we both
exchange something superfluous for something necessary.”” (p 157)
As Marx
says, the modern economists of his day frequently used Condillac's
argument, yet a simple response to it was provided by Le Trosne, who
wrote,
“If
both the persons who exchange receive more to an equal amount, and
part with less to an equal amount, they both get the same.” (Note
2, p 157)
Marx continues,
“If
commodities, or commodities and money, of equal exchange-value, and
consequently equivalents, are exchanged, it is plain that no one
abstracts more value from, than he throws into, circulation. There is
no creation of surplus-value. And, in its normal form, the
circulation of commodities demands the exchange of equivalents. But
in actual practice, the process does not retain its normal form. Let
us, therefore, assume an exchange of non-equivalents.” (p 158)
and,
The same is
true if buyers are able to buy at 10% below Value.
“The
creation of surplus-value, and therefore the conversion of money into
capital, can consequently be explained neither on the assumption that
commodities are sold above their value, nor that they are bought
below their value.” (p 158)
In similar
terms, Marx dismisses the argument put forward by Torrens, who
writes,
““Effectual
demand consists in the power and inclination (!), on the part of
consumers, to give for commodities, either by immediate or circuitous
barter, some greater portion of ... capital than their production
costs.”” (p 159)
Marx
comments,
“The
fact that the owner of the commodities, under the designation of
producer, sells them over their value, and under the designation of
consumer, pays too much for them, does not carry us a single step
further.” (p 159)
and he
quotes Ramsay to the same effect,
“The
idea of profits being paid by the consumers, is, assuredly, very
absurd. Who are the consumers?” {G. Ramsay: “An Essay on the
Distribution of Wealth.” Edinburgh, 1836, p. 183.} (Note 4 p 159)
The only
basis on which this could result in profit is if there were a class
of people that,
“only
buys and does not sell, i.e., only consumes and does not produce. The
existence of such a class is inexplicable from the standpoint we have
so far reached, viz., that of simple circulation. But let us
anticipate. The money with which such a class is constantly making
purchases, must constantly flow into their pockets, without any
exchange, gratis, by might or right, from the pockets of the
commodity-owners themselves. To sell commodities above their value to
such a class, is only to crib back again a part of the money
previously given to it. The towns of Asia Minor thus paid a yearly
money tribute to ancient Rome. With this money Rome purchased from
them commodities, and purchased them too dear. The provincials
cheated the Romans, and thus got back from their conquerors, in the
course of trade, a portion of the tribute. Yet, for all that, the
conquered were the really cheated. Their goods were still paid for
with their own money. That is not the way to get rich or to create
surplus-value.” (p 159-60)
No comments:
Post a Comment