The Labour Theory of Value
is a theory of Objective Value. It is not, as some people have
confusedly believed, an Objective Theory of Value! There is a
significant difference between the two.
A theory about anything can
claim to be objective, which is what the latter is asserting, but in
reality, because all theories are based on the perspectives of those
who advocate them – the way they see the world – they are always
to one degree or another subjective. Marx never claimed that his
theory was objective in this sense. He advanced it unashamedly from
the perspective of the working-class. That is not the same thing as
falsifying data, being dishonest etc. On the contrary, it is being
all the more honest for proclaiming from the beginning that the way
you see the world depends upon your position within it.
What Marx advanced was a
theory that was based upon the idea that
Value
itself was objectively measurable, just as the length of a table, a
football field etc. is objectively measurable, using some agreed upon
standard measure of length. The standard measure of length in the
case of Labour is
Abstract Labour.
There was nothing radical in
Marx's proposal of such a Labour Theory of Value, because at the time
he did so, the idea that Labour was the basis of value was accepted
by nearly all economists. Nor was that something that had only
recently been arrived at. The notion that Labour was the basis of
value went back thousands of years. At about the same time both
Plato
in Greece and Mang-Tsze in China attempted to theorise commodity
production in the context of the division within the commodity
between Use Value
and Exchange Value.
Both Plato and
Aristotle
put forward a Labour Theory of Value. Aristotle attempted to develop
a Theory of Value based on Use Value, but he found himself stuck in a
dead end. In the coming centuries, it was the idea that for the
commodity it was its Exchange Value not its Use Value, that was
determinant, and it was on that basis that the role of Labour in
determining that Value played the central role.
Nor was it anything unusual
that Labour should occupy this position. For millennia around the
globe it had in practice played that role as I have set out
here.
As described there, it is the performance of labour that is seen as the basis of value in the ideas of a whole series of thinkers such as Thomas Aquinas , and Albertus Magnus , Duns Scotus and Ibn Khaldun. Similarly, the Physiocrats believed that Labour was the source of all wealth, but living at a time prior to the domination of Capital, they believed that it was only agricultural Labour that produced Value.
The Physiocrats were followed by the Classical economists. They put forward the idea that Value was objectively measurable according to the labour-time required for production. For example, Benjamin Franklin wrote,
“By labour may the value of silver be measured as well as other things. As, suppose one man is employed to raise corn, while another is digging and refining silver; at the year’s end, or at any other period of time, the complete produce of corn, and that of silver, are the natural price of each other; and if one be twenty bushels, and the other be twenty ounces, then an ounce of that silver is worth the labour of raising a bushel of that corn. Now if by the discovery of some nearer, more easy or more plentiful mines, a man may get forty ounces of silver as easily as formerly he did twenty, and the same labour is still required to raise twenty bushels of corn, then two ounces of silver will be worth no more than the same labour of raising one bushel of corn, and that bushel of corn will be as cheap at two ounces, as it was before at one ceteris paribus. Thus the riches of a country are to be valued by the quantity of labour its inhabitants are able to purchase.”
And
“trade in general being nothing else but the exchange of labour for labour, the value of all things is, as I have said before, most justly measured by labour.”
And Adam Smith wrote,
“The real price of everything, what everything really costs to the man who wants to acquire it, is the toil and trouble of acquiring it. What everything is really worth to the man who has acquired it, and who wants to dispose of it, or exchange it for something else, is the toil and trouble which it can save to himself, and which it can impose on other people…. It is natural that what is usually the produce of two days’, or two hours’ labour, should be worth double of what is usually the produce of one day’s or one hour’s labour.”
A look at the writings of
these Classical Economists shows that it was on this basis that their
economic analysis was conducted. For example,
David Ricardo
in his theory of Comparative Advantage
sets out the argument in precisely these terms of the labour-time
required for production of various commodities in two different
countries.
Marx studied all of these
theories in considerable depth, and set about resolving the
inadequacies and contradictions within them. For example, it was
clear that the idea implicit in Franklin's formulation that all
labour was an equal measure of Value could not hold, any more than
all feet can act as an equal measure of length. Different types of
Labour – the labour of a joiner, a tailor, an accountant – vary
just as one person's feet vary compared to another's. In the same
way that a standard “foot” was arrived at as an abstraction from
real feet, to act as a measure of length so Abstract Labour had to be
considered the measure of Value.
But, also Adam Smith had
found himself in a contradiction, because he believed, as did Ricardo
and others, that what workers sold was Labour. But, if the value of
a commodity was determined by the Labour required to produce it, say
10 hours (£10), then if the worker was paid the Value of the Labour
they had supplied, which also equalled 10 hours (£10), then it was
impossible for the capitalist to extract a surplus value from the
worker. Marx resolved this contradiction by demonstrating that the
Surplus Value
arises because what the worker sells is not Labour, but Labour-power.
Finally, Ricardo's followers
like John Stuart Mill recognised that market prices did not tally
with Exchange Value, but found themselves stuck in a contradiction
trying to reconcile the fact. Ricardo argued that these prices moved
around the Exchange Value, which acted as a long term pivot. But, it
was clear that this could not be correct either, because if
commodities, produced by different industries with different
organic compositions of capital,
sold at their Exchange Values, then rates of profit would diverge
wildly. All economists recognised that there would be a tendency for
rates of profit to equalise, because capital would automatically move
from where rates were low to where they were high. Marx reconciled
this contradiction too by developing the concept of
prices of production,
which demonstrated the way in which Exchange Value forms the basis
upon which surplus value arises, but this surplus value, existing as
a fund at the level of Capital in General, of the economy as a whole,
the exchange value or monetary equivalent of the society's surplus
product, is then shared out by Capital on the basis of the share of
the total capital provided by each industry. On this basis, the
Value of the economy's output is determined by the labour-time
required for its production, so the sum of Value will equal its
monetary equivalent, the sum of prices. That is in fact
tautological, because the amount of labour-time required to produce
all of the output is determined, and thereby determines the total
Value produced – Value is Labour-time – whilst the Exchange Value
of all of that production is nothing other than the rate at which it
exchanges against money i.e. its price!
In other words, the total
Value (not to be confused with Exchange Value) of the economy's
production is equal to the labour-time required for its production.
This Value can then be expressed using Marx's
value form.
Here the total Value stands in the position of
relative form of value.
That is the thing whose Value is being expressed relative to some
other commodity. That other commodity here is the Money Commodity.
It stands in the position of
equivalent form of value.
In other words, money expresses the Value of the economy's total
output as an Exchange Value, but that Exchange Value, by definition
here is also its price, because the Exchange Value of any commodity
measured in terms of money is its price - again not to be confused
with Price of Production or Market Price.
As a theory of Objective
Value, the Labour Theory of Value stands in contrast to Theories of
Subjective Value, which form the basis of orthodox economics. These
theories place their emphasis not on the Exchange Value of
commodities, but on their Use Value. That is they argue that Value
is subjective, depending upon the utility that each consumer obtains
from any commodity as opposed to all other alternatives. To use the
comparison with length used earlier, these subjective theories of
value derive the Exchange Value/Price of a commodity on the basis of
the sum of all the individual valuations of it made by consumers.
The equivalent would be measuring the length of a table not by using
a standard metre, but instead asking a large number of people to rank
its length in relation to everything else, and then arriving at some
average length!
I've dealt with some of the
basic problems of orthodox economics based on this subjective theory
of Value in my series
reclaiming economics.
The fact that Marx develops
a theory of objective value, of course, does not mean that his
overall economic theory of capitalism can be reduced to some
similarly objective, and, therefore, mechanical basis. On the
contrary, Marx's analysis of Capitalism has to deal with the
subjective nature of the psychology of individuals, be they workers,
capitalists or consumers, precisely because his theory is a theory
about real people, not automatons.
So, for example, Marx states
that although there is an absolute minimum of wages, determined by
what is physically needed to ensure the reproduction of the
working-class, there is no such minimum for the rate of profit. Yet,
Marx is fully aware that below a certain level, capitalists will tend
to stop investing in productive capital, and instead spend on
unproductive consumption, speculation and so on. There is no
objective basis for determining when that will occur, because it
depends upon the subjective decisions of the capitalists themselves,
about what they think is an adequate level of reward.
Similarly, although an
objective theory of value can determine what the Exchange Value/Price
of any commodity is, it cannot determine what the level of demand for
that commodity will be at that price. That again depends upon the
subjective assessments of consumers. And Marx was fully aware of the
idea of diminishing marginal utility derived from commodities the
more of them are consumed. In other words, he understood the
principle of Price elasticity of demand.
In fact, it forms a central aspect of his theory of overproduction.
No comments:
Post a Comment