The Ricardian
School, went beyond that theory and recognised that Surplus Value
stemmed from the productiveness of labour, though Ricardo himself
simply assumed and accepted its existence. However, they failed to
pursue that logic to its conclusion to identify the source of surplus
value in the exploitation by capital of that labour. And for good
reason.
“In fact these bourgeois
economists instinctively saw, and rightly so, that it is very
dangerous to stir too deeply the burning question of the origin of
surplus-value.” (p 483)
Marx is scathing of John
Stuart Mill.
“Mill says:
'The cause of profit is that labour produces
more than is required for its support.'
So far, nothing but the old story; but Mill
wishing to add something of his own, proceeds:
'To vary the form of the theorem; the reason
why capital yields a profit, is because food, clothing, materials and
tools, last longer than the time which was required to produce them.
He here confounds the duration of labour-time
with the duration of its products. According to this view, a baker
whose product lasts only a day, could never extract from his
workpeople the same profit, as a machine maker whose products endure
for 20 years and more. Of course it is very true, that if a bird’s
nest did not last longer than the time it takes in building, birds
would have to do without nests.”
Marx continues, quoting Mill again,
“'We thus see,' he
proceeds, 'that profit arises, not from the incident of exchange,
but from the productive power of labour; and the general profit of
the country is always what the productive power of labour makes it,
whether any exchange takes place or not. If there were no division of
employments, there would be no buying or selling, but there would
still be profit.'
For Mill then, exchange, buying and selling,
those general conditions of capitalist production, are but an
incident, and there would always be profits even without the purchase
and sale of labour-power!
'If, he
continues, 'the labourers of the country collectively
produce twenty per cent more than their wages, profits will be twenty
per cent, whatever prices may or may not be.' This is, on
the one hand, a rare bit of tautology; for if labourers produce a
surplus-value of 20% for the capitalist, his profit will be to the
total wages of the labourers as 20:100. On the other hand, it is
absolutely false to say that 'profits will be 20%.'
They will always be less, because they are calculated upon the sum
total of the capital advanced. If, for example, the
capitalist have advanced £500, of which £4OO is laid out in means
of production and £100 in wages, and if the rate of surplus-value be
20%, the rate of profit will be 20:500, i.e.,
4% and not 20%.” (p 483-4)
Marx criticises Mill for arguing that
capitalist relations are universal. A peculiar claim, as Marx
remarks, given that, at that time, it was only the case for a small
percentage of the Earth! Mill had also suggested that instead of the
capitalist paying wages to the worker, it would be possible for the
worker, if he had the means, to wait until they had produced the
commodity, and then be paid its full value. Mill notes that in this
case, the labourer is really a capitalist providing some of the funds
needed for production.
Marx notes,
“Mill might have gone further and
have added, that the labourer who advances to himself not only the
necessaries of life but also the means of production, is in reality
nothing but his own wage-labourer. He might also have said that the
American peasant proprietor is but a serf who does enforced labour
for himself instead of for his lord.” (p 484)
In other words, what
Marx is criticising here is that Mill in no sense grasps the idea of
economic relations also being social relations. What Marx is getting
at, is that a surplus product does not simply arise automatically,
and certainly its appropriation by some other person is not some
simple economic reality that arises spontaneously. It is determined
by social relations, which themselves arise as part of a long process
of historical development. That these social relations, and this
historical development is itself a product of economic relations that
arise “behind men's backs”, as a consequence of changes in the
productive forces, is the key to understanding Marx’s Historical
Materialism. In short, it is a dialectical process by which one
development, acts as a feedback loop on to the other.
The natives living off the Sago tree,
had the potential of surplus labour, but there was no imperative that
drove them to engage in it. They were masters of their own destiny,
in that regard. But, had the land and the trees on it, been owned by
a landlord, then they would have been forced to pay rent to that lord
for being able to obtain their subsistence from the tree. The rent
would be in the form of surplus labour, labour undertaken over and
above what was required for their own subsistence, but required for
the subsistence of the landlord. The same is true of the US
peasants. They were able to acquire land for nothing, or for very
little during European colonisation. As a result, all the labour
they undertook on that land was for their own benefit. But, as soon
as all the land in the US, like the land in Europe, becomes the
property of a small class of people, that small class is able to
charge those who farm it a rent. They are able to force the
producers to do surplus labour for them. This force might not be the
same kind of force as that used by a slave owner against a slave, but
it is force all the same, it is the force that stems from economic
power, consequent upon property ownership. This is also the basis of
Marx’s differentiation between labour being formally subordinated to
capital, and then its real subordination to capital, when the worker has
no real alternative but to supply their labour-power as factory
labour.
Mill goes on to argue that the worker
was really a capitalist too, who lends a part of his labour-power to
the capitalist by selling it below the market price, and then
receives it back with interest! But, as Marx has demonstrated,
workers do not sell their Labour power below its market price. It is
the fact that the value they produce is greater than the value of
their labour power which is the source of the surplus value.
Back To Part 3
Forward To Chapter 17
Back To Index
Back To Part 3
Forward To Chapter 17
Back To Index
No comments:
Post a Comment